Friday, October 10, 2025

Fastiggi and Sonna on Catholicism and capital punishment (Updated)

Recently, theologian Robert Fastiggi was interviewed about the topic of the Church and the death penalty by apologist Suan Sonna on his podcast Intellectual Catholicism.  Fastiggi’s views are the focus of the discussion, but Sonna, who largely agrees with him, adds some points of his own.  Their main concern in the discussion is to try to defend the changes Pope Francis made to the Church’s presentation of her teaching on the subject. 

I appreciate their civility, and Fastiggi’s call at the end of the interview for charity in dealing with those who disagree.  But their attempt fails.  Much of what Fastiggi has to say are reheated claims that I have already refuted in past exchanges with him, such as the two-part essay I wrote in response to his series on the death penalty at Where Peter Is.  (You can find it here and here.  The essay was reprinted as a single long article in Ultramontanism and Tradition, edited by Peter Kwasniewski.)  Fastiggi simply repeats his assertions without acknowledging, much less answering, my rebuttals.  He also makes some new claims, which are no more plausible than the older ones.  Let’s take a look.

A straw man

In any fruitful discussion of this topic, it must constantly be kept in mind that there are two questions that need to be clearly distinguished.  First, is the death penalty intrinsically wrong?  And second, even if it is not intrinsically wrong, is it nevertheless morally better never to resort to it?  To answer “Yes” to the first question is to say that capital punishment of its very nature, and regardless of the circumstances, is wrong, and thus can never even in principle be used.  But someone could answer “No” to the first question and still answer “Yes” to the second.  To take this view is to say that while in theory the death penalty could be justified in certain circumstances, in practice those circumstances never obtain, at least not today, and that the moral considerations that tell against its use outweigh those that speak in favor of it.

People who comment on the topic of Catholicism and capital punishment very frequently ignore this distinction.  The result is that they often talk past one another and the discussion generates more heat than light.  Now, at the beginning of their conversation, Fastiggi and Sonna are, to their credit, careful to note the distinction.  But unfortunately, later in their discussion, they ignore it, and this leads them to attack a straw man.

In particular, Fastiggi claims (after the 35 minute mark in the video) that “people say, well, the Church has always taught, always allowed for the [death penalty].”  Arguing against this, Fastiggi cites some Fathers of the Church who were against capital punishment, and concludes that “it’s almost like a myth, this 2,000 year old tradition, but if it’s repeated enough by commentators and writers, then people begin to believe it.”  Similarly, Sonna remarks (around the 45 minute mark) that “a lot of people have this impression that the Church, as if it were this uniform block, this constant unchanging permanent wall, has just consistently said the death penalty’s fine, you know, go ahead and do it.”  But in fact, he continues, “historically, there was an uneasiness at times with the death penalty.”  Fastiggi and Sonna make a big deal out of this theme, as if it is a damning point against Catholic defenders of the death penalty.

But not so fast.  For here too we need to distinguish two claims, namely:

(1) The Church always taught for 2,000 years that the death penalty is not intrinsically wrong.

(2) The Church always taught for 2,000 years that the death penalty is not only not intrinsically wrong, but that it is generally a good idea and should be used.

I know of many Catholic defenders of capital punishment who have asserted claim (1), including myself.  But claim (1) is by no means a “myth.”  It is demonstrably true, as Joseph Bessette and I document in detail in our book By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic Defense of Capital Punishment.  Indeed, in his own book on the subject, E. Christian Brugger, the foremost Catholic theologian who argues against capital punishment – and someone who even claims that the death penalty is intrinsically wrong – admits that (1) is true.  In fact, even Fastiggi and Sonna appear to concede it.  Fastiggi acknowledges that the Fathers he cites “don’t necessarily challenge the state’s right to [execute],” but merely argue against exercising that right.  And Sonna admits that “maybe we can’t dispute that the state has the right, technically, to do it.”

By contrast, claim (2) is indeed false, for just the reasons Fastiggi gives.  But I cannot think of a single person who endorses claim (2) in the first place.  (Certainly Joe Bessette and I explicitly acknowledge in our book that some Fathers and popes held that it was morally better not to resort to the death penalty.)  So, when Fastiggi cites what certain of the Fathers say as evidence against a “myth” he alleges many are peddling, he is attacking a thesis that no one in fact holds.  It seems otherwise to him and to Sonna only because they ignore the distinction between (1) and (2).

Misrepresenting John Paul II

Sloppiness of this kind often leads Fastiggi to misrepresent the views of his opponents and the nature of their disagreement with him.  It also leads him to misrepresent a pope he appeals to in defense of his position, namely Pope St. John Paul II.  About seven minutes into the video, Fastiggi suggests that the Church now condemns not only killing the innocent, but “intentional killing” as such.  He says:

The reason why the Church has now developed her teaching to be opposed to capital punishment is because it involves intentional killing, and then the question of course of whether or not a murderer loses human dignity and the right to life.  And really, the turning point of this was St. John Paul II.  In Evangelium Vitae number 9, he says not even a murderer loses his dignity.

After the 50 minute mark, Fastiggi returns to the theme, and says:

I think a leap was made with the understanding that punishing people by intentionally killing them is an offense against the inviolability of life.  The theoretical question is, does a serious crime take away the right to life?  And John Paul II answered that in Evangelium Vitae 9.  That was the breakthrough, that not even a murderer loses his dignity and right to life.

This is sleight of hand.  It is true that Evangelium Vitae 9 says that “not even a murderer loses his personal dignity.”  But the encyclical nowhere says that a murderer does not lose his right to life.  Instead, it speaks of “the absolute inviolability of innocent human life,” “the inviolable right to life of every innocent human being” and again, of “fundamental human rights, beginning with the right to life of every innocent human being”; it says that “as far as the right to life is concerned, every innocent human being is absolutely equal to all others”; it teaches that “a law which violates an innocent person's natural right to life is unjust and, as such, is not valid as a law”; and it calls for “unconditional respect for the right to life of every innocent person” (emphasis added).  And it explicitly allows that the execution of those guilty of the gravest offenses is permissible “in cases of absolute necessity.”  That would not be possible if the murderer never loses his right to life.

It is true that Evangelium Vitae also says that bloodless means are preferable where possible because they are “more in line with human dignity” and “more in conformity to the dignity of the human person.”  But notice that that does not entail that capital punishment is not at all in line with human dignity, only that it is less in line with it.  (Compare: To say that Ricky is more talented than Fred does not entail that Fred is altogether untalented; to say that Ethel is more intelligent than Lucy does not entail that Lucy is altogether unintelligent; and so on.)  So, from the claim that (a) not even a murderer loses his dignity, together with the claim that (b) the death penalty is less in line with human dignity than milder punishments, it simply does not follow that (c) capital punishment is flatly incompatible with the murderer’s dignity, and neither does it follow that (d) the murderer does not lose his right to life.  Nor, again, does John Paul II draw those conclusions.

Perhaps Fastiggi would say that John Paul II should have drawn those conclusions, and that in failing to do so he was being inconsistent.  But there are several problems with such a response.  First, it wouldn’t change the fact that John Paul II did not in fact draw them, and thus did not in fact say the things Fastiggi attributes to him.  Second, for the reasons I have given, the conclusions do not in fact follow logically from John Paul II’s premises, so that the pope was not being inconsistent.  Third, if there are two ways of reading a papal document, in one of which it contains an inconsistency and in the other of which it does not, the second is to be preferred.  Hence, for that reason alone, we should reject Fastiggi’s reading.  Fourth, Fastiggi’s reading would imply that John Paul II was not only not consistent with himself, but also contradicted his predecessors – such as Pope Pius XII, who taught:

Even when it is a question of the execution of a man condemned to death, the State does not dispose of the individual's right to live.  It is reserved rather to the public authority to deprive the criminal of the benefit of life when already, by his crime, he has deprived himself of the right to live. (Address to the First International Congress on the Histopathology of the Nervous System, 1952, emphasis added)

Certainly, implicitly to accuse one pope (John Paul II) of inconsistency and another pope (Pius XII) of grave moral error is a strange way to try to defend a third pope (Francis)!

In any event, Joe Bessette and I provide a very detailed analysis of John Paul II’s teaching at pp. 144-82 of our book.  As we demonstrate there, when one considers the entirety of the evidence (and not just the usual cherry-picked phrases Catholic opponents of capital punishment like to quote), it is crystal clear that the pope’s teaching was in no way an alteration or even development of traditional doctrine, but simply a prudential judgment about how to apply that doctrine to contemporary circumstances.  Like so many of our critics, Fastiggi offers no response at all to the arguments we give there, but pretends they don’t exist.

Obfuscating on Pope Francis

Beginning at about 12 minutes into their discussion, Fastiggi and Sonna argue that Pope Francis has, in any event, not actually taught that the death penalty is intrinsically wrong.  They focus on the pope’s 2018 revision to the Catechism, and suggest that it implicitly acknowledges that capital punishment is permissible in theory, and simply teaches that it is inadmissible under current circumstances.

This is a defensible position, as far as it goes.  I have always myself acknowledged that the revision can and should be read in such a way that it is not teaching that capital punishment is intrinsically evil.  But that is only part of the story.  For one thing, the problem with the revision is that this is not a natural reading of it.  The revised text characterizes the death penalty as “an attack on the inviolability and dignity of the person.”  On a natural reading, that seems to imply that capital punishment is intrinsically at odds with human dignity (rather than being at odds with it only if certain conditions fail to hold), and thus intrinsically wrong.  Yes, it need not be read that way, but magisterial statements should be clearly consistent with traditional teaching, not merely consistent with it on a strained reading.

For another thing, other magisterial statements made during Pope Francis’s pontificate are much harder to reconcile with the traditional teaching.  For example, in a 2017 address, the pope asserted that “the death penalty is an inhumane measure that, regardless of how it is carried out, abases human dignity.  It is per se contrary to the Gospel” (emphasis added).  The italicized phrases are most naturally read as claiming that capital punishment is always and intrinsically wrong.

Some might reply that this entails only that the death penalty is contrary to the higher demands of Christian morality, not that it is contrary to natural law.  That would be bad enough, because (as I have shown elsewhere, such as in this article) the traditional teaching of the Church is that it is not contrary to Christian morality any more than it is contrary to natural law.

But to make matters worse, the declaration Dignitas Infinita, issued by the DDF during Francis’s pontificate, implies that capital punishment is contrary even to natural law.  For it asserts that “the death penalty… violates the inalienable dignity of every person, regardless of the circumstances,” and that this dignity is grounded in “human nature apart from all cultural change.”  The declaration also asserts that human dignity must be upheld “beyond every circumstance,” “in all circumstances,” “regardless of the circumstances,” and so on.  Here there is no wiggle room for saying that the document judges capital punishment to be contrary to human dignity only if certain conditions are not met.  For it flatly asserts that it violates human dignity “regardless of the circumstances.”  Nor is there any wiggle room for saying that the document nevertheless allows in principle for such a violation of human dignity under certain circumstances (which would be a bizarre idea in any case).  For it explicitly says that human dignity “prevails in and beyond every circumstance, state, or situation the person may ever encounter,” and so on.  The logical implication of all this is that capital punishment is absolutely ruled out as always and intrinsically wrong.  And that straightforwardly contradicts traditional teaching.

Sonna, at least, appears to acknowledge that the traditional teaching cannot be reversed.  So, if he is going to be consistent, he will have to admit that these statements issued during Francis’s pontificate are problematic – that they are poorly formulated at best, and erroneous at worst (which is possible in non-ex cathedra magisterial statements).

Parallel doctrinal reversals?

Fastiggi is another story.  At around 40 minutes in, he says: “But hasn’t the Church definitively taught that the death penalty is allowed?  No, it hasn’t.”  And earlier, at around 25 minutes in, he says that “even if the Church has not yet, maybe someday she’ll say it’s intrinsically immoral, but because it had been accepted for so long we don’t need to say that right now.”

But Fastiggi is simply mistaken.  When all the relevant evidence is taken account of, it is manifest that the doctrine that the death penalty is not intrinsically wrong has been taught by both scripture and the Church in an irreformable manner.  I set out some of this evidence in a long Catholic World Report article from some years back, and Joe Bessette and I do so in greater depth in our book.  Fastiggi says nothing even to acknowledge, much less answer, these arguments.  He merely begs the question against them.

Fastiggi also says that even if the Church does not hold that the death penalty is intrinsically wrong, it doesn’t follow that its teaching against it is merely a prudential judgment which Catholics need only respectfully consider but not necessarily follow.  For the Church has the authority to prohibit even certain practices that are not inherently wrong.  Fastiggi gives the example of cremation, which was for a long time prohibited by the Church but now is permitted under certain circumstances.  He also cites polygamy and divorce, which were tolerated under the old covenant but have been forbidden under the new covenant.

Fastiggi is right about that much, but these facts don’t suffice to show that the Church can do more than issue a non-binding prudential judgment against use of the death penalty.  The reason is that it is the state and not the Church which has the responsibility and right under natural law to do what is necessary to ensure the safety of the community.  This is why, after setting out the criteria for fighting a just war, the Catechism goes on to say that “the evaluation of these conditions for moral legitimacy belongs to the prudential judgment of those who have responsibility for the common good” (2309).  In other words, the Church can teach that a war is just only when the cause is just, there is a serious chance of success, no other options are likely to work, and so on.  But the Church does not have the expertise or authority to determine how these criteria apply in a particular case.  For example, it does not have the relevant expertise to determine whether some option other than war would suffice to repel an aggressor in a particular case, or whether a certain military strategy is likely to succeed.  These are matters of prudential judgment, and it is the state rather than the Church that has the right and responsibility to make that judgment.

But the same applies, mutatis mutandis, to capital punishment.  The revision to the catechism claims, for example, that modern systems of imprisonment are sufficient to protect others against the most dangerous offenders.  But the Church has no more expertise on that sort of issue than it does on military strategy.  If government officials have good empirical reason to believe that the death penalty saves lives – for example, if they have evidence that it has a significant deterrent effect, or that it is needed to protect prison guards or other prisoners from the most violent offenders – then they have just as much a right under natural law to utilize capital punishment as they do to fight a just war. 

This sort of reasoning does not apply to cremation, which is why it is not an interesting parallel to the case of capital punishment.  The examples of polygamy and divorce also do nothing to help Fastiggi’s case, and not just because (unlike capital punishment) the state does not need to keep them open as options in order to do its job of protecting society.  There is also the following glaring disanalogy: The New Testament explicitly forbids divorce and clearly opposes polygamy too, as has the Church ever since.  But the New Testament explicitly allows capital punishment (e.g. in Romans 13), as has the Church ever since.  Cremation, polygamy, and divorce thus offer no precedent for an absolute prohibition on capital punishment.

Fastiggi and Sonna suggest other alleged doctrinal reversals that they think provide a precedent for a reversal on capital punishment.  But they are all bad analogies that provide no support whatsoever for such a reversal.  For example, Fastiggi points to the fact that theologians were once free to disagree about the Immaculate Conception, but later the Church made a dogmatic pronouncement on the matter so that such legitimate disagreement is no longer possible.

The problem with this purported analogy should be obvious.  To teach that capital punishment is intrinsically wrong would directly contradict what the Church had consistently taught for 2,000 years and what she had always understood scripture to teach.  Proclaiming the dogma of the Immaculate Conception involved nothing remotely like that.  In particular, it in no way involved the Church contradicting some doctrine she had previously taught.

Fastiggi alleges that there is also a parallel between capital punishment and the case of torture.  He contrasts a passing remark on the subject from Pope Innocent I, which left its use open, with the more recent teaching of the Church condemning torture.  Here too the alleged parallel is spurious.  The Church holds that scripture cannot teach moral error, and she has for two millennia acknowledged that scripture repeatedly sanctions capital punishment.  But there is no such scriptural sanction for torture.  The Church has also for two millennia herself consistently and clearly taught that capital punishment can under certain circumstances be licit, to the point of including this doctrine in major teaching documents such as the catechisms of Pope St. Pius V and Pope St. John Paul II.  The teaching was also endorsed by the Fathers (even those who opposed the use of capital punishment in practice), has been consistently affirmed by the Church’s greatest theologians (including many Doctors of the Church), and routinely endorsed in approved manuals of moral theology.  None of this can be said of torture. 

Fastiggi and Sonna also suggest that the development of the Church’s teaching on slavery provides a precedent for a change on capital punishment.  But this alleged parallel too is phony.  For one thing, here too Fastiggi and Sonna muddy the waters by ignoring long-established and crucial distinctions.  For the word “slavery” is ambiguous.  What most people think of when they hear this term is chattel slavery, which involves claiming ownership of another human being in the way one might own an animal or inanimate object.  The Church does indeed teach that this is intrinsically evil, but she has never taught otherwise.  Indeed, she has condemned this practice for centuries (as I document in my book All One in Christ: A Catholic Critique of Racism and Critical Race Theory).  

There are, however, less extreme forms of servitude that the Church has taken to be at least in theory not unjust.  In particular, there is penal servitude, which is forced labor in punishment for a crime.  The idea here is that if the state can, in punishment for a sufficiently grave crime, take away an offender’s liberty for a prolonged period of time (even for life), then it can also require him to work.  And there is indentured servitude, a prolonged period of labor without payment as a way to repay a debt or in exchange for some benefit.  The idea here is that if someone can legitimately enter a work contract, or have his wages garnished in order to pay a debt, then by extension he can make himself a servant in order to pay a debt.

The trouble with these practices is that in concrete circumstances they are fraught with moral hazard, and were often used to rationalize what amounted to chattel slavery (such as when captives taken in war were enslaved on the spurious grounds that they were guilty of the offense of fighting an unjust war, and thus could be forced into penal servitude).  Hence, moral theologians settled on the view (quite correctly, I would say) that when all relevant moral considerations are brought to bear, it is clear that they ought flatly to be banned altogether.

There is also the consideration that in scripture, slavery is merely tolerated as an institution that happened to exist, rather than put forward as a positive good.  By contrast, the death penalty is not merely tolerated, but in some cases is positively sanctioned (not only in the Mosaic law, but in other contexts such as Genesis 9 and Romans 13).

So, when all the distinctions are made, the argument that “the Church reversed herself on slavery, so she can reverse herself on capital punishment” falls apart.  There was no such reversal, and thus no precedent for a reversal on capital punishment.

Magisterial credibility

This brings us to Fastiggi’s remarks about Genesis 9 and Romans 13, where he repeats claims that I have already refuted in my previous exchange with him.  And once again, he simply ignores rather than answers the objections I raised there.  I direct the interested reader to that earlier essay of mine.  (In particular, see the sections titled “Genesis and the death penalty” and “The Mosaic Law versus the Gospel?”)

Fastiggi acknowledges that, in the instruction Donum Veritatis, the Church affirms that Catholics have the right respectfully to raise questions about deficient magisterial statements and ask for clarification.  He says that this nevertheless gives Catholics no right to “dissent” from the teaching of the Church.  I agree with him about all that.  But Fastiggi seems to think that it rules out the sort of respectful criticisms that I and others with the relevant expertise have raised.  It does not, and I have many times given arguments that show that it does not.  These arguments too are ones that Fastiggi simply ignores rather than tries to answer. 

For example, the criticisms I have raised with respect to the 2018 revision of the Catechism have nothing to do with “dissenting” from some teaching of the Church.  Rather, the whole point is that the teaching is unclear – that it is far from obvious exactly what it is that Catholics are being asked to assent to.  True, the revision declares that the death penalty is now “inadmissible.”  But the trouble is that the force of this teaching is not obvious.  I have argued that there are only two ways to read it.  On the one hand, it might be read as claiming that the death penalty is intrinsically wrong and thus “inadmissible” in an absolute and unqualified way.  The problem is that this would contradict scripture and tradition, and thus amount to a doctrinal error (something that can occur in non-ex cathedra statements). Moreover, even Fastiggi and Sonna acknowledge that this is not the right way to read it.

But when we take account of all the relevant considerations (both from within the document and from the larger tradition of the Church), the only other way to read it is as saying that the death penalty is “inadmissible” unless certain conditions hold (such as that resort to it is necessary in order to protect society).  And if this is the case, then the teaching amounts to a non-binding prudential judgment.  For the “unless” part is not something concerning which the Church has any special authority.  For example, whether capital punishment has a significant deterrence effect, and whether modern prison systems really do afford the means of protecting others from all violent offenders, are empirical matters of social science, not matters of faith or morals. 

For seven years now, Fastiggi and I have been arguing about this issue, and in all that time I have never gotten a clear answer from him about what a third possible interpretation would look like.  In any event, if someone asks me “Do you dissent from the teaching of the revision of the Catechism?” my answer is “No, I do not dissent from it.  I assent to it, and interpret it in the only way I know of that makes sense – namely, as a non-binding prudential judgment.”  I also say, however, that the revision is badly formulated and potentially misleading.  And I have every right respectfully to raise such a criticism, by the norms set out in Donum Veritatis.  Fastiggi and others may continue to yell “Dissent!” but yelling is all they would be doing.  I have yet to hear an actual argument showing that my position amounts to dissent.

I acknowledge that my criticism of Dignitas Infinita goes beyond this.  Here, I think we have a document that is not merely ambiguous, but very hard (at best) to defend from the charge of flatly contradicting scripture and tradition and thus being erroneous.  But if someone has a plausible way of reconciling it with scripture and tradition, I’m all ears. 

Even if it is indeed in error, however, this is possible in non-ex cathedra documents.  Indeed, Fastiggi himself is implicitly committed to this thesis.  For, again, he holds that the Church could end up teaching that capital punishment is intrinsically immoral.  And if that were correct, it would follow that for two millennia, the Church got things gravely wrong on matters of basic moral principle and biblical interpretation.  That is a very radical claim, and indeed far more radical than anything I have said.  If I am right, then one pope has gotten things wrong about capital punishment.  If Fastiggi is right, then every previous pope who has taught on this topic has been wrong, as have the Fathers and Doctors of the Church (and indeed scripture itself).  Fastiggi likes to paint views like mine as extreme, but in fact it is his views that are extreme. 

The fact that he presents them politely and under the guise of obedience to the magisterium doesn’t change that one whit.  It is the content of the views that matter, and the content is radically subversive of the credibility of the Church, because it implies that the Church may have been gravely in error about a matter of natural law, the demands of the Gospel, and the proper understanding of scripture for her entire history until now.  And if she could be that wrong for that long, what else might she be wrong about?

At about one hour and three minutes into the interview, Fastiggi says, with no sense of irony: “There has to be trust in the Holy Spirit’s guidance of the magisterium.  And that’s what I find missing in many of these papal critics.  They don’t trust the Holy Spirit.”  Yet Fastiggi is the one suggesting that the magisterium may have, for two millennia, consistently erred about a grave matter of natural law, Christian morality, and scriptural interpretation.  Fastiggi is the one suggesting that the Holy Spirit might have permitted this.  But what is more likely – that that is the case, or that a single pope (Francis) issued a badly formulated catechism revision and permitted the DDF to slip a doctrinal error into a declaration?  I submit that, if the Holy Spirit truly is guiding the magisterium, the scenario I posit is manifestly more plausible than the one Fastiggi is positing.

The reality is that the critics do trust in the Holy Spirit’s guidance of the magisterium.  They trust that the Holy Spirit would not have allowed the Church to be that wrong for that long about something that important, so that it must be those who now contradict the past magisterium who are mistaken.  This has always been theoretically possible, because the Church has always acknowledged that non-definitive exercises of the magisterium can fall into error.  Indeed this has in fact happened before in the case even of papal teaching, as the famous examples of popes Honorius I and John XXII illustrate.  And Fastiggi’s own position entails it.  If, as he insists, it may turn out that two millennia of past teaching of the magisterium on capital punishment was wrong, then it follows logically that it is also possible that it is instead Pope Francis’s statements on the subject that are wrong.  And as I have shown elsewhere (here and here), the Church has also always affirmed that there can be cases where the faithful may respectfully criticize the magisterium, even a pope, for teaching contrary to the tradition.

What Fastiggi never seems to appreciate is that his approach damages the credibility of the magisterium by appearing to saddle it with what, in logic, is known as a “No True Scotsman” fallacy.  Suppose I say “No true Scotsman would be an empiricist,” and you respond “But David Hume was an empiricist!”  And suppose I reply “Well, then David Hume must not really have been a true Scotsman,” and that I insist that everybody has for 250 years been misinterpreting all the evidence that seems obviously to show that he was an empiricist.  Needless to say, this would not lend me or my thesis any credibility at all, but would do precisely the opposite.  It would reveal me to be intellectually dishonest and unwilling to look at the evidence objectively.

Now, the First Vatican Council declared that “the Holy Spirit was promised to the successors of Peter not so that they might, by his revelation, make known some new doctrine.”  The Second Vatican Council stated that “the living teaching office of the Church… is not above the word of God, but serves it, teaching only what has been handed on.”  Pope Benedict XVI taught that the pope “must not proclaim his own ideas… he is bound to the great community of faith of all times, to the binding interpretations that have developed throughout the Church's pilgrimage.”

But the liceity in principle of the death penalty has for two millennia been consistently taught by the Church, and has for two millennia been understood by the Church to be the teaching of scripture, which is the word of God.  Hence, for a pope to teach that the death penalty is intrinsically immoral would manifestly be a case of attempting to “make known some new doctrine.”  It would manifestly be a case of putting himself “above the word of God” instead of “teaching only what has been handed on.”  It would manifestly be a case of attempting to “proclaim his own ideas” rather than being “bound to the great community of faith of all times.”

Fastiggi, however, takes the view that if a pope were to teach such a thing, then the conclusion we should draw is that the liceity in principle of capital punishment must after all not really ever have been the teaching of scripture; that it must not really be a “new doctrine” but somehow implicit in what scripture and the Church have always taught; that it must not really after all have been among “the binding interpretations” to which a pope must conform himself.  And that is like dogmatically insisting that Hume must not really have been a true Scotsman after all.  It gives aid and comfort to Protestant and skeptical critics of Catholicism, who argue that the Church’s claim to continuity with scripture and tradition is a sham – that at the end of the day, the popes will just teach whatever they like and then arbitrarily slap the label “traditional” on it.

It may be that Fastiggi is not sufficiently sensitive to this problem, whereas I have always emphasized it, in part because of the differences in our academic and intellectual contexts.  Fastiggi is a theologian teaching at a seminary, the primary job of which is the formation of priests.  And it seems that he writes pretty much exclusively for Catholic audiences.  I’m a philosopher teaching at a secular college, who often writes on matters of apologetics.  And my writing is directed as much to the general public as it is to fellow Catholics.  When Fastiggi sees Catholics criticizing even obviously deficient magisterial statements, even in a respectful and well-informed way, his instinctive reaction appears to be: “It’s unseemly for Catholics to be doing that, no matter what the pope says!  Just keep quiet, and trust providence to sort it out.”  When I see Catholics tying themselves in logical knots trying to defend obviously deficient magisterial statements, my instinctive reaction is: “Those are manifestly terrible arguments, you’re making Catholicism look ridiculous!  Just frankly admit that there’s a problem, and trust providence to sort it out.”  What Fastiggi and I agree about is that providence will sort it out, but we disagree about what form this might take and what role respectful criticism of deficient magisterial statements can play.

At the end of the day, though, such psychological speculations are not what matter.  What matters is what the evidence of scripture, tradition, and the entirety of the magisterial history of the Church (not just the last few years of it) have to say.  And as I have argued, that evidence tells decisively against Fastiggi’s position.

UPDATE 10/18: At Substack, Suan Sonna offers some comments which clarify his position.  I thank him for his civil and charitable reply.

81 comments:

  1. It's remarkable how many people, even quite intelligent people, have difficulty recognizing the distinction between the idea that we should work to make society such that we don't need the death penalty, which should in any case be restricted to genuinely protecting the common good and done only with grave caution, rarely, etc., and the idea that the death penalty is morally wrong in and of itself, by its very nature. It's particularly pernicious here, because everyone who rejects the latter gets slapped with an undifferentiated 'pro-death-penalty' label, which is much as if you labeled anyone who believed it is not always wrong to kill someone trying to murder you with a 'pro-killing' label.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Hi Brandon,

      Yes, it's completely unnecessary and counterproductive for anti-capital punishment Catholics constantly to resort to the most extreme characterizations of their opponents and of the death penalty itself. The Fathers who urged the state not to exercise its right to execute managed to avoid doing that. So why can't modern opponents? It reinforces the suspicion that for many of them, the death penalty issue is a stalking horse for other doctrinal changes -- that they want to push for the most extreme sort of change on this issue precisely because they know that would open the door to others.

      Delete
    2. I fear that underneath the bulk of opposition to the DP is an intense this-worldly view, a secular mind-set that this life is the only life to consider; on that mind-set, it is "impossible" for a human being to lose his right to life, because that's "ALL HE HAS" as the basis for other rights: denying his right to life is tantamount to denying his very personhood. But a Christian view rejects this completely: his immortal soul is a far better ground for his dignity and rights, yet at the same time it expressly allows that death is NOT an "ultimate" indignity to his person, as God can even use his death for good - both for his OWN good and for that of others.

      I believe that most (probably nearly all) of the Church's individuals who are totally opposed to DP and who are not deeply steeped in the Church's history and biblical understanding, are operating in a kind of sympathetic conformity with the mainstream secular humanists whose educated elite have articulated a pseudo-moral-high ground for the anti-DP position. In effect, they are practicing secular humanists even while they believe they are solid Christians. The ones who bother to read snippets of recent Church doctrinal documents - but not earlier ones to achieve perspective - falsely believe that the recent documents constitute explicit affirmation of that pseudo-moral-high ground as articulated by secular humanists, not noticing that even where there is overlap between the Church's expressed conclusions and those of the secularists, it is on a different basis (at least, when it is articulated and not merely hand-waved as if axiomatic and manifest to all).

      In practice: we should completely discount the apparent majority view of those "in" the Church on this, as "they know not what they do". I that I were able to say that this majority excludes the bulk of the bishopric.

      Delete
    3. It's one example of several of how Catholic minds and sensibilities have been corrupted by thoroughly marinating in the essentially liberal and modernist assumptions that pervade our institutions.

      Delete
  2. Hey Prof

    This is such a comprehensive article! It's really good!

    On the point of torture, I would actually suggest an article by Dr David Decossimo where he goes into depth as to what separates torture from mere killing. I don't know if you have come across it but I think it would be quite useful to you an article you could cite.

    Overall, I think that, if you could add anything to this article, it's probably the fact that the principle of proportionality is concerned with the degree to which the perpetrators will has deviated from the good that it ought to pursue.

    This could probably forestall arguments that try to attack the death penalty from the like to like standpoint i.e we wouldn't torture a torturer etc.

    I suppose one key point that often is neglected in this debate but deserves attention is the mode of capital punishment. I think you addressed this once briefly in your article Augustine on Capital Punishment. Interested readers can check it out. It's a great article.

    I think it would strengthen the case for the death penalty by pointing out why certain methods of punishment we find too gruesome for our times.

    For example to show that a punishment like rectal feeding is intrinsically evil is quite difficult. But I think Fr Brian Harrison in article has a good general argument against it where he mentions that torture could attract sexual perverts. I think it can also facilitate tendencies like a lust for violence and domination over other people (This similar to what Augustine thought about gladiator fights)

    One could expand on it by pointing out that in our times such things could easily go viral on video camera due to the widespread prevalence of such technology and the general tendency to record things for the sake of views , guards themselves could do it or could be bribed to do and the overall effect on society would be to lend legitimacy a kind of legitimacy to such disordered desires.

    Couldn't a similar argument be made against the death penalty? I would say it can be made against certain methods but not all.

    For example , to apply a classical natural law analysis, the rectum is responsible for expelling waste from the body, waste which ought not to be discharged anywhere but in its proper place as it is disease prone, foul smelling etc. By nature this is one of those act which requires that the person have control over that faculty such as to avoid stinking up a place. That is why it's one of the first activities that is introduced to us as kids and that old people feel embarassed to ask for assistance as they lose motor control.

    Any action rectal feeding or anything else involving the rectum, exercises a kind of control or degree of power over an individual that is extremely unusual, and this would legitimise such kind of lust for control. I mentioned how things go viral.

    In contrast something like choking (hanging) or lethal injection represents a degree of control that is mundane, it could of course be something that triggers people's lust for violence but at the same time something like a choke hold is a routine part of formal martial arts and self defence or subduing a criminal, it can be classified as something that a person ought to know precisely for the purposes of self defence.It's something that already is very common in society and thus death by hanging or lethal injection wouldn't "by itself" involve facilitating the promotion of disordered tendencies. It's an act that is already mainstream Someone with a disordered attraction to it could just as easily come across it in other places. In contrast , the vitalization of a punishment like rectal feeding is what would make a fringe act mainstream and thus ought to be prohibited.

    Anyways I hope that this slightly long comment could be of use to you Prof. Thanks for all your work. I am grateful.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Thanks, Norm. The question of which methods are appropriate is a good one and more needs to be said about it. Suan raises the point at the end of the interview that there is something wrong with people taking a celebratory tone toward execution, and I agree with him about that. I also think it should not be drawn out or gruesome and that it should be solemn, with an emphasis on urging the offender to repent and to offer his punishment up as a penance, praying for him, and so forth. I'll write on this in more depth at some point.

      Delete
    2. Would gladly look forward to it Prof. You have from time to time briefly addressed it, Your article and Rehabilitation was also an article I found to be quite interesting where I think you were responding to Brugger. Obviously your more recent article on corporal punishment is relevant.

      Yes repentance is important. And obviously not taking a celebratory tone. And emphasizing prison ministry of priests etc.

      Do you think my analysis above based on degree of control exerted and societal implications it could entail is a good way of drawing some distinctions between actions to rule out certain kinds of punishments as I did above?

      If it's not too much trouble.

      Delete
    3. I would not object to a state declaring a state-wide day of prayer and penitence on a day of execution, to counteract any sense of celebration of the killing.

      Delete
    4. Newman has a beautiful description of the death penalty as practiced in a Catholic state in his "Difficulties of Anglicans," and it is exactly the scenario you describe. Then there too is the example of St John Neumann of Philadelphia (the noose of a prisoner whose conversion he obtained can be seen at his shrine museum).

      Delete
    5. Just putting in another request for Prof's opinion of my analysis :). Would really appreciate it

      Delete
  3. “Do you dissent from the teaching of the revision of the Catechism?” my answer is “No, I do not dissent from it. I assent to it, and interpret it in the only way I know of that makes sense – namely, as a non-binding prudential judgment.” I also say, however, that the revision is badly formulated and potentially misleading.

    The problem here is that the 'potentially' is really misleading. The revision is actually 'misleading' -- except that it was almost certainly intended to be 'misleading,' so calling it misleading in fact looks to be disingenuous trading on ambiguity. If you do not assent to the natural reading, if you admit that it is badly formulated and misleading, then it seems you are withholding assent, which is indeed a form of dissent. Qualified dissent, but still real dissent. And good for you! You should dissent from false teachings of false teachers.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Well, "dissent" is ambiguous. On the everyday usage of the word, any disagreement counts as a kind of dissent. But the word has a narrower, technical meaning in Catholic contexts that has to do with refusing to assent to some teaching that the Church puts forward as binding on Catholics (which includes infallible teachings but other things too). But Donum Veritatis explicitly says that respectfully raising questions about deficient magisterial statements does not count as "dissent" in this sense.

      Delete
    2. It seems obvious that it is not possible to either assent or dissent unqualifiedly from an inherently unclear teaching. You can say, "I assent because the pope taught it, but I'm not really sure what he is teaching," but that's not 'real' assent, and not worth much (I dare say) in the eyes of God or man. Mutatis mutandis for dissent.
      That said, I wonder if you (can/should) really assent to JPII's teaching that the death penalty is to be 'absolutely' avoided except in case of 'absolute necessity' (i.e., prudentially considered!), because it is inherently "more in line with human dignity" to use bloodless means of punishment, regardless of the crime being punished. Is that position too not contrary to the teaching of scripture (esp. Rom 13:4) and the sound Catholic theological tradition?? Is JPII not implying that Paul is wrong to say that the state is God's minister to execute vengeance on evildoers, when he wants to limit the role of the state to protecting the innocent?
      And so also, I agree we shouldn't crassly 'celebrate' when an evildoer is executed; but we should take a sober satisfaction in the upholding of justice and rightly ordered obedience to the divine will. And we should lament the deeds of those who have used their magisterial office to obscure and subvert the divinely established moral order.

      Delete
    3. I believe it is not inconsistent with Donum Veritatits to argue that JPII made an editorial mistake in putting his prudential judgment into a Catechism. It's not the place. Fine for putting it into the encyclical (such as Evangelium Vitae), but a Catechism is for timeless truths that are well settled not only as doctrine but also as phrasing. Similarly, he changed the phrasing for how to apply the "safety" basis for DP 3 times in 5 years: the 1992 Catechism, EV, and the 1997 Catechism all employ different phrasing having importantly different senses. His own thought on the issue was changing, and he shouldn't have saddled a Catechism with that process.

      More significantly is his use of the following:

      Assuming that the guilty party's identity and responsibility have been fully determined, the traditional teaching of the Church does not exclude recourse to the death penalty, if this is the only possible way of effectively defending human lives against the unjust aggressor.

      The problem is more apparent if you separate it into 2 propositions instead of 1:
      A: The traditional teaching of the Church allows recourse to the death penalty.
      B: Traditional teaching of the Church allows recourse to the death penalty if and only if this is the only possible way of effectively defending human lives against the unjust aggressor.

      (In other articles, Professor Fastiggi argued for this inserted sense using "only if" as the proper interpretation of the Latin, and I admit his claim is plausible, though I cannot find the Latin text to review it.)

      Set aside the theological issue for the moment: both A and B make historical claims. The historical accuracy of A is unquestionable. The historical accuracy of B is not. Indeed, it is hard to justify it AT ALL in history, much less establish it as reliable and certain. The best that can be said of B (if this is indeed the best reading of the text) is that it is a backwards reading of JPII's theological thesis (for the "only if" part) into a less-than-perfectly-definitive prior Church analysis of why and when DP is allowable. One could not even propose that JPII's theological thesis (ignoring its historical preface) was the preferred or leading contender for the state of the question. If it was articulated at all (and I have had trouble finding that, but maybe that's me), it was a minority opinion at best, and more likely it was a highly dubious minority opinion, as it opposes a wealth of better-articulated positions that speak to the common good as a whole.

      I am not a theologian, and I am not as confident of this as I would like, but I don't think JPII's phrasing can be taken as putting a magisterial approval on the HISTORICAL aspect of the claim, i.e. "the magisterium hereby approves the aforesaid minority and dubious thesis and hereby MAKES it the historically affirmed position". I think the historicity stands or falls on the evidence, not on magisterial shielding. And it's not defensible historically.

      If I am right about that, then the passage should be interpreted in the following way: A is true, and the thesis in B (about "only if") is hereby proposed to be the only basis on which A is true. The "traditional teaching" claim ONLY applies to A.

      This would leave us free to DEBATE the "only if" part of B on its own terms, i.e. allow us to hash it out fair and square without deference to a presumption it is true because it was the traditional teaching.

      I think some people would like to claim that B is really to be understood as saying merely that "IF DP is ever allowed, it is only ever allowed for safety of persons", (a conditional claim) and then add in Francis to be saying "but in fact, even safety of persons cannot EVER justify DP." I think this would represent creeping distortion of "traditional teaching," one mistake piled on top of another.

      Delete
    4. I concur with David that careful thinkers should be cautious on accepting the proposition that DP is necessarily "less in line with human dignity". I think that once you get that punishment itself is "more in line with human dignity" as it affirms the moral value - and responsibility - of the criminal, you can't easily get DP somehow departs from that model. The proportionality aspect that is built into moral worth (and grounds rewards as well as punishments) leads inexorably to DP as fitting to certain crimes and criminals, and that JUST IS "more in keeping" with the dignity of rational beings with moral freedom. One might argue that "well, yes, the criminal deserves death, but it is not fitting for civil society be the instrument of that death, it belongs to God. But this runs square up against Genesis 9:6 where God assigns it explicitly to humans, and the passage as a whole seems to be explaining natural law, (referring to man's nature in the beginning).

      I think the requirement to lean against using DP except when "necessary" should be related to the whole good which the civil government ought to promote: there are common goods (justice, and virtue), public goods (a general sense of safety), and personal goods (freedom from this prisoner's future depredations, AND this prisoner's own future physical life) in the balance: a presumption that the last item trumps ALL OTHER considerations so completely as to make them irrelevant has...virtually nothing to recommend it philosophically.

      Delete
    5. As I've long argued, the dignity rhetoric is vague and unnecessary at best and at worst a Trojan horse for ideas that can't be reconciled with natural law and tradition. It should never have become so central. My point in the article is that even if one grants it, JP2 did not actually use it in a way that has the implications that Fastiggi (and others, such as Brugger) think it has.

      Delete
  4. Re the “practical” rationale that modern prison systems are sufficient to prevent/deter further criminal acts by the murderer…. This should not to be easily conceded. Powerful gangster/organized criminals continue issuing orders, including death warrants, from their prisons.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Yes indeed. That is one of several ways in which the suggestion that modern prisons suffice to protect people just isn't true. Joe Bessette and I discuss this in our book, and in the eight years since it appeared, I think not a single critic has responded to that point (if memory serves). Just crickets. It shows how unserious most of them are.

      Delete
    2. I'm not an opponent of the death penalty (not in principle, at least). I'm not a Catholic or a believer in natural law either, so I'm not sure whether any comment I make on this article, which is directly about the Catholic perspective, would be relevant. But I think the problems of prison violence and recidivism are indeed some of the strongest arguments for maintaining the death penalty. However, aren't there places (such as some European countries) that don't have the death penalty and have very low rates of prison violence and recidivism (much lower than, say, the U.S.)? Mind you, I'm not sure how much of that is really because of factors such as better prison conditions versus how much other factors that governments may not be able to do much about, such as population size or culture, are causing it. I think it's something that's worth discussing in this debate, as I have seen it brought up elsewhere.

      Delete
  5. This was wonderful Ed. Very clearly written!

    ReplyDelete
  6. Ed: “I acknowledge that my criticism of 'Dignitas Infinita' goes beyond this. Here, I think we have a document that is not merely ambiguous, but very hard (at best) to defend from the charge of flatly contradicting scripture and tradition and thus being erroneous. But if someone has a plausible way of reconciling it with scripture and tradition, I’m all ears.”

    A couple of points about the relevant sentence in 'Dignitas Infinita' 34 that make an interpretation consistent with the previous magisterium more defensible:

    First, repeating the text itself: ‘Here, one should also mention the death penalty, for this also violates the inalienable dignity of every person, regardless of the circumstances.’

    The official text, as printed in 'Acta Apostolicae Sedis' (An. et vol. CXVI, N. 5, 3 May 2024, p. 608), is the Italian:

    ‘Bisognerà pure qui menzionare il tema della pena di morte: anche quest’ultima, infatti, viola la dignità inalienabile di ogni persona umana al di là di ogni circostanza.’

    1. The English version is accurate enough – except that it adds a comma after ‘person’, which is not in the original Italian after ‘persona umana’ (and the English also leaves out ‘human’ as a translation of ‘umana’, which is not relevant here).

    In a natural reading, adding the comma increases the plausibility of the interpretation that the phrase ‘regardless of the circumstances’ relates directly to the verb ‘violates’. This makes the sentence more amenable to the interpretation that the death penalty is being indicated as intrinsically evil, since it would violate human dignity regardless of circumstances.

    However, omitting the comma (which is the accurate thing to do) increases the plausibility of the interpretation that the phrase ‘regardless of the circumstances’ relates directly either to ‘inalienable dignity’ or ‘every person’ - acting in either case as a redoubling of the affirmation of inalienability.

    The meaning would be, on this interpretation: every person regardless of circumstances has this dignity intrinsically, and the death penalty violates that. (Thus it is neither affirmed nor denied that the death penalty violates this inalienable dignity intrinsically, regardless of circumstances: the weaker interpretation is left open that 'for practical purposes, in our world’s current social circumstances', it virtually always violates dignity.)

    ReplyDelete
  7. 2. The sentence has a footnote reference (56) to the revised paragraph of the Catechism (n. 2267), and to the CDF’s 'Letter to Bishops Regarding the New Revision of Number 2267 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church on the Death Penalty' nn. 7-8.

    If there is ambiguity (as there is, especially with the comma omitted), we need to interpret the sentence in view of the footnote. And the footnote indicates that the CDF understands and intends its sentence in 'Dignitas Infinita' to be reiterating, or at least significantly supported by, the texts referred to.

    As Ed has said, the revised Catechism paragraph is itself at least open to an interpretation consistent with the previous magisterium.

    Also, the 'Letter to Bishops' explicitly affirms that the doctrine of the Catechism is ‘in continuity with the preceding Magisterium’ (7) and ‘is not in contradiction with the prior teachings of the Magisterium’ (8).

    Granting for the sake of argument that this absence of contradiction cannot be created by mere fiat if there does appear to be a fairly evident contradiction, the text of the 'Letter' does at least establish that Pope Francis and the CDF did not intend to be interpreted as contradicting the past magisterium. So if there is a plausible interpretation of the relevant texts that harmonizes with this claim of non-contradiction, then that is the interpretation we must take.

    Finally, the 'Letter to Bishops' (7) makes it the dignity of the person ‘that is not lost’ regardless of circumstances, ‘even after having committed the most serious crimes’ - so the fact that 'Dignitas Infinita' makes reference to this passage, reaffirms the interpretation of 'Dignitas Infinita' that it intends ‘regardless of circumstances’ to relate directly to ‘the inalienable dignity of every person’, not to the verb ‘violates’.

    In short: if the revised Catechism is open to (or indeed, requires) an interpretation consistent with the previous magisterium, then likewise for 'Dignitas Infinita'.

    ReplyDelete
  8. The issue runs deeper than simply the application of the death penalty. Abolitionists argue for a schizophrenic juridical system, in essence utilitarian, in which the application of justice is a tertiary end, if it is an end at all. This, if carried to its logical conclusion would collapse the justice system itself. It undermines the entire logic behind it, which always must be primarily justice.

    ReplyDelete
  9. You argue, with characteristic precision, that the Magisterium’s recent language on the death penalty represents not a development but a departure, a contradiction of two millennia of consistent teaching. You frame this as a matter of doctrinal fidelity, a defence of what the Church has always taught against innovations that threaten her credibility. Yet what appears to you as reversal may in fact be a transformation in the metaphysical horizon within which the same truth is now perceived. The Church’s moral imagination has not abandoned its foundations; it has deepened them.
    For centuries, Christian reflection unfolded within a linear conception of time: birth, earthly existence, death, and an “afterlife” extending along that same continuum. Within that view, death marked the transition from the temporal to the eternal, and to kill, even justly, was simply to move that moment forward. The logos of the person, their eternal vocation, remained intact; only the timing changed. Thus, capital punishment could be accepted as legitimate, since it seemed only to adjust the chronology, not the essence, of a human life.
    But as the Church’s metaphysical imagination has matured, drawing especially on St Maximus the Confessor’s vision of creation as an ascent into the Logos, a different understanding has emerged. This maturation, evident throughout twentieth-century ressourcement theology, marks what Henri de Lubac called “the recovery of the mystery of participation,” by which “the supernatural is no longer conceived as a second story built upon nature, but as the interior transformation of all being by grace” (Surnaturel, 1946, p. 470). Creation is no longer understood as a neutral stage upon which God occasionally acts, but as a dynamic movement already being drawn into Him.
    Pope Benedict XVI articulated this shift with striking clarity: “eternity is not an unending succession of days in the calendar, but something more like the supreme moment of satisfaction, in which totality embraces us and we embrace totality” (Spe Salvi §12). Likewise, he taught that “time itself becomes a dimension of God’s self-communication” (Eschatology: Death and Eternal Life, 1988, p. 115). The temporal, therefore, is not a flat line leading to eternity, but a field already irradiated by it. Death, in this light, is not merely a step along a horizontal continuum; it is the terminus of the earthly form of life that can be transposed vertically into the eternal.

    (cont.)

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Every moment of earthly existence thus possesses ontological weight: it is not simply one instant among others, but a participation in the eternal form toward which it is destined. As Hans Urs von Balthasar writes, “Each finite moment bears within itself the whole drama of the eternal decision” (Theo-Drama V, 1998, p. 83). Nicolas Loudovikos, interpreting Maximus for our age, calls this the “verticalisation of temporality,” the transformation of linear time into “a Eucharistic ascent of all being into its eschatological fulfilment in the Logos” (Analogical Identities, 2019, p. 214). From this horizon, to end a life prematurely, even under the pretext of justice, is not merely to alter its duration but to deform the total offering of that life as it is being drawn into God.
      Seen thus, the Church’s renewed opposition to the death penalty is not a denial of her past but a deepening of it. You are right that the Church cannot contradict herself, but she can grow in her apprehension of what her truths entail. Killing in self-defence or in a just war remains morally licit because it preserves the possibility of life and order. Yet when the state executes one who no longer poses a direct threat, it no longer acts as guardian of life but as agent of its interruption. The metaphysical horizon has shifted from time measured along a line to time gathered up into eternity.
      This same understanding clarifies why euthanasia and abortion are wrong, not only because they violate a commandment, but because they disfigure the logos of a human life meant to be offered to God in its fullness. The final days or years of a suffering person are not meaningless intervals before heaven; they are part of the temporal pattern that God intends to gather into eternity. Likewise, to destroy an unborn or newly baptized child is not to hasten its beatitude, but to sever the form of life by which God intended to glorify Himself through that person’s unfolding.
      If you read the Church’s language on dignity through this metaphysical lens, you may see that her deepening resistance to the death penalty arises from the same seamless vision that grounds her opposition to euthanasia and abortion. What is at stake in each case is the eternal significance of temporal being. As Joseph Ratzinger observed, eternity is not endless duration but “the interpenetration of time by divine presence.”
      To trust the Magisterium, then, is not to imagine that it arbitrarily changes course, but to believe that the Spirit continues to draw the Church into the fullness of truth. What you regard as a change of judgment may in fact be the unveiling of the same truth within a transfigured horizon: that every life, in every moment of its earthly duration, is already a participation in the eternal, and that to preserve that life is to cooperate in the world’s ascent into God.

      Delete
    2. I welcome the idea that the popes (and others) want to push a development of doctrine on this (and other) issues. I object to the idea that it is "development" to simply throw out a new idea not obviously in line with the past teaching and claim "you get from here to there by development". No: development is to provide the pathway by which you get from here to there.

      And I decline to follow along with re-imagining life meaning to what you suggest representing that pathway that tells us the DP is inherently improper, from the past teaching.

      “a Eucharistic ascent of all being into its eschatological fulfillment in the Logos” (Analogical Identities, 2019, p. 214). From this horizon, to end a life prematurely, even under the pretext of justice, is not merely to alter its duration but to deform the total offering of that life as it is being drawn into God.

      It doesn't do the job: God can (and, apparently, WILL) accomplish that "Eucharistic fulfillment of all being" regardless of whether we end it a bit earlier or not. Or, take a baby who dies because some tired pharmacist filled out a prescription wrong: why isn't it the case that baby's life being ended prematurely "deform the total offering of that life as it is being drawn into God"? Or a 4 year old who dies in an accident? No: God's infinite power can take even a criminal's well-deserved death and make it conform to His Plan just fine, and our actions will not defeat that Plan. And justice tells us that the death of the murderer at his execution is NOT "premature" at all, but exactly the time that God Himself allotted, "by which God intended to glorify Himself through that person’s unfolding."

      There appears to be a fundamental disconnect between what you imagine to be the eschatological fulfillment and the meaning of acts in this life: in order for acts in this life to "have meaning", they have to have some effect as to the ultimate form of the fulfillment as to its particulars in us at that final denouement. If God WILL accomplish his end - the same end regardless of whether we kill this murderer or not - then his death doesn't "mean anything" (and neither does his life). But at the same time, if that ultimate end doesn't reflect our acts of justice differently than if we were instead to act unjustly, then that again shows our actions - and our lives in their particularities - are meaningless.

      God will take our acts of justice and perhaps magnify them incomprehensibly in His glorious culmination. But He cannot at one and the same time do that with our acts of justice, AND say that some acts of justice are unjust because they changed how He "was going to" unfold that person's life if we hadn't done those acts of justice. The explanation doesn't explain, and the "development" doesn't develop. All we're offered is "Now we understand better and ...(energetic hand-waving..."inadmissible".

      And it's inconsistent to say that

      Killing in self-defence or in a just war remains morally licit because it preserves the possibility of life and order. Yet when the state executes one who no longer poses a direct threat, it no longer acts as guardian of life but as agent of its interruption.

      and also to say that the Church (in Francis's new 2267) has said DP is wrong in all cases. He has RULED OUT the DP where needed to defend from that criminal's future attacks, it's "inadmissible" as a violation of dignity.

      Delete
    3. Tony, you’re begging the question. Your argument assumes from the outset that any killing which God permits cannot constitute a rupture in what He intends. That collapses the distinction between God’s permissive will and His active will. There must be some moral standard that renders an act wrong in itself, regardless of whether it ultimately falls within God’s omnipotence or His providential plan for creation.

      That is why the analogy of murdering baptized infants is instructive. We rightly recoil from such an act and grieve the lives cut short. But why, if nothing real is lost? Our horror presupposes that there is an objective deprivation, something truly damaged in the order of grace, even though God can bring good from evil.

      Delete
    4. Tony, you’re begging the question. Your argument assumes from the outset that any killing which God permits cannot constitute a rupture in what He intends. That collapses the distinction between God’s permissive will and His active will. There must be some moral standard that renders an act wrong in itself, regardless of whether it ultimately falls within God’s omnipotence or His providential plan for creation.

      I agree that there is a standard that renders the act wrong in itself, and decline your offered basis. No, I accept from the outset that following God's directives to put some people to death because they deserve it due to grave crimes is what "cannot" cannot constitute a rupture with what He intends. It is your attempt to re-interpret Genesis, Exodus, etc all the way through Romans - differently from the way the Fathers interpreted them - to mean that God's directive must be understood NOT to mean that we should put such people to death, that is circular. The only ground you offer for such a vast re-interpretation is that "they are part of the temporal pattern that God intends to gather into eternity" and that such pattern is violated by their "early" death. You circularly assume it is "early" merely because it is not due to natural causes, but I decline that because it's still following what God said to do and that can't violate his intention.

      You seem to provide that proper description of why the murder of a child - and his "early" death therein - is wrong, is given by such phrasing as "temporal pattern that God intends to gather into eternity". Such phrasing FAILS to give a reason that doesn't apply equally to the child dying by illness or accident. The full description includes the malice of the murderer, which makes him a guilty agent, and renders him due a punishment. The Bible is replete with God warning and advising us that his Providential will and Plan knows all about the evil things that evil men will do to us, that "he meant it for evil, but God meant it for good", by which God will (for us) transform such suffering into our eternal benefit: it's PART of our eternity. A person's unjust death is just one more of those sufferings that He will use in that eternity.

      The reason the murderer's act is filled with malice and evil is not that "it doesn't conform to God's Providence", at least not simply. It is true that it doesn't conform to God's antecedent and preceptive will, but that itself is further resolvable to the fact that the act is contrary to human nature. Man as an intelligent and social being is made for love of neighbor, and the malice involved in murder directly contradicts that.

      The man who ACTS on a determination to murder, and yet fails (either by natural obstacles, or by God's simply not allowing the act's intended result, e.g. St. Denis's beheading didn't kill him), is just as evil and just as much deserves death, even though in concrete fact his act has NOT defeated God's antecedent will in regards to the life of the person he tried but failed to kill. So it is not the death itself - and it's interference with God's antecedent will for that victim - that renders the criminal liable for punishment, but the evil intention and choice to act on it. Before you commit murder, God's antecedent will is that you not murder. After you do (and before you repent), God's consequent will is that you be subject to the retributive principle of justice, not because the murdered person can no longer "fit into" the antecedent plan of creation for him (he still can if God protected him), but because of your malice and willed choice to act on it.

      Delete
    5. Thanks for your detailed response. Just one further question:

      Is it good or bad for an infant himself to be murdered immediately after baptism?

      Delete
    6. Of course it is bad for the infant - or any innocent person - to be murdered: killing harms the human being, because death conflicts with his nature as a living being. And the manner of death is always an injury to the body. Of course you know this.

      It is just as true that kidnapping an innocent person harms the person, as it prevents them from acting according to their own will, i.e. it conflicts with their nature as rational beings to see goods, judge them, and freely act on that judgment: to freely choose their own coming and going, to decide on their manner of life, etc.

      So, my question to you is: is it bad for a properly convicted criminal to be put in prison so that he cannot choose his own coming and going, decide his own manner of life, etc?

      Delete
  10. Pope Leo opposes the application of the death penalty and so did the three popes who preceded him. Were they all wrong? I will accept their judgment over that of the moderator of this blog.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Two of those 4 popes expressly supported the in principle licitness of the death penalty while opposing it in practice. Francis opposed it in practice and chose to be highly ambiguous on it's licitness in principle. Leo's position on that is yet to be given. I will accept the clear determination of the two of four that spoke clearly on it's licitness over the judgment of others that Francis would have been explicitly against the licitness of the death penalty had he been clear on the subject, and the speculation of others for what Leo will or won't do.

      Delete
  11. Very, very interesting discussion right here!

    One thing that the guys who tell us that the death penalty is "unjust," unreflective (or even deliberately) do is eschew the victim from the picture and keep the full focus on the perpetrator (I'm not saying the gentleman in the video did that, I'm just saying that people who held this position are very often soft-hearted towards the criminal). But, I will not focus exclusively on this theological matter -- even though I think it is a moral defect and a grave sin to be merciful towards the criminal and cruelly disregard the victim.

    The point I want to focus on is that the so-called "penalists" or "humanist penalists" often overlook (again, either irreflectively or deliberately). To be sure, the death penalty IS MOST DEFINITELY NOT a matter of mere crime prevention, "instrumentalizing the man," or "negative prevention by fear," as they usually say -- these are just secondary effects. The truth is that the death penalty is to serve justice, firstly towards the victim and their family or even the society at large -- and, sometimes, it's the only way to serve justice, given the gravity of the crime.

    It doesn't take one far to see how unjust it is to keep a convicted murderer alive. Take Brazil as an example. A man associated with criminal factions or crime syndicates goes on to murder the family of the whistleblower who, courageously, denounced the criminal schemes. The murderer will be jailed, sustained by taxpayers' money, and will not even serve two decades in jail (since here in Brazil, you can't serve more than 30 years in prison, and, most of the time, these sentences are not fully dutied because the criminal is "entitled" to a progression of regime that he could serve in probation, out of the jail).

    The little example I gave above, which is unfortunately part of reality, leaves us with the following question: what kind of 'justice' do we get in the mind of society, the victim's family, and even in the mind of the perpetrator himself, if a murderer could simply "walk" and live on his life after committing one of the gravest sins of all time? By permitting even the minimal injustice of leaving a murderer alive, the criminal system only raises the feeling of injustice and civil unrest, and, undeniably, the victim, who is the most crucial part of the criminal picture, remains unserved by justice.

    ReplyDelete
  12. I think the history of the Church’s doctrinal treatment of DP, from Innocent I’s statement of the issue in 405 until 2018, has been clear and incontrovertibly in favor of DP being morally licit under the natural law. The history before that may be more ambiguous. Here is, I think, a fair and balanced description:

    1. The apostles accepted DP: (a) They concretely indicated approval, (St. Paul, in Romans 13:1-4; (b) they clearly called it forth (St. Peter in Acts 5:1-10), (c) they recorded explicit affirmation of it (Luke 23:41 (the Good Thief) ), and (d) otherwise simply allowed its existence without opposition or demurral (the Gospels as a whole). Everything they wrote that touches on the use of the DP at least implicitly accepts it, and nothing they wrote disapproves of it as a general matter.

    2. After the apostles, for much of the next 250 years (before Constantine), the early Fathers were mixed: of the ones who spoke on it (not all by any means), most of them clearly disapproved of its practice in some references. Some of them seemed to give as reasons a position that sounds general in its disapproval, and yet in other references they seemed to accept it, thus they muddled their own opposition. Origen and Tertullian, two of the most promient early teachers, expostulated against it (and opponents of DP often pull out quotes from these two), but in other places they admitted its liceity. Of the ones that wrote against DP and there appears to be no passages from them that also accepted it, generally their disapproval of it is ambiguous, in that it is less than clear whether their opposition was against it in principle and for all cases, or in practice given the mores of the times and its particulars.

    3. In the 4th century, after Constantine, most of the Fathers that spoke on it clearly supported its liceity in principle even if they broadly opposed its regular and easy practice, and often urged against using it.

    Under the principles of development of doctrine, the explicit determination of Innocent I in 405 interprets this past ambiguity of the record, in favor of the LICEITY of the DP under both the natural law and under the Gospels, and pushed the Church to model the sometime opposition of earlier Fathers into an antipathy based on practices and particulars, not based on a per se violation of proper dignity. The next 1590 years (to JPII’s Catechism) represent an unbroken affirmation of Innocent’s determinative conclusion and further refinement of the thinking behind which the moral liceity of DP is understood not to be a per se violation of the proper dignity of a criminal lawfully found to be guilty of grave crime.

    Moral, philosophical, and theological necessity dictates that development of doctrine ONLY GOES IN ONE DIRECTION. Even if the record of the early Fathers appears at times to allow a conclusion that maybe the DP is per se immoral, the clear determination of Innocent on the issue and the development of doctrine that actually occurred over 1660 years after Constantine does not permit us to allow that “appears at times” to represent any foundation for NOW arguing that DP is illicit. The Church has spoken on that ambiguity and settled it. You can’t keep using it in later times, when the development process laid it to rest – that’s what the one-way direction implies. There had been NO ambiguity on the issue for 1590 years, including on how to read the ambiguity of the earlier years.

    Consequently, while it was true for a period that the record was ambiguous, after the Church addressed that ambiguity, even that period is no longer ambiguous, and it is more correct to say that there is a 2000-year record wherein the Church firmly teaches the liceity of the DP.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. I know this won't surprise or persuade you, but I'm not impressed by the evidence you put forward in favor of the idea that the apostles accepted the death penalty. Romans 13 is a notoriously difficult text, since some of the things Paul says there are (taken literally) self-evidently false; in fact, to believe too strongly in 1-4 would be an argument against the Christian faith, as it would require that Jesus himself (as well as all the martyred disciples) merely got what was coming to them. People recoil from that reading, but it's a hard one to escape unless you take Paul merely as saying that the state serves a practical purpose and that it is in the best interest of Christians (as a persecuted minority) not to engage in lawlessness, lest they be struck down by the sword of the Roman soldier or dragged off to prison by the magistrate. As for the Gospels, I hope I don't have to explain that the purpose of the thief's dialogue in Luke 23 is to make a theological point about Jesus as an innocent sufferer, not offer a commentary of the liciety of the death penalty (and anyways, I assume you're not arguing that it is ever permissable to put a common thief to death.) It's true that Peter seems to use his power as an apostle to smite Ananias and Sapphira, but the exact causality is unclear, and Luke is deliberately cagey about how the pair perished (they seem to just keel over and die). Again, hardly a clear-cut case, and also no comfort to the supporter of DP unless lying to a bishop also carries a death sentence. It's not enough to say "the apostles accepted the DP" if you don't also accept what they believed *about* the DP.

      But most importantly, how can we say that the Gospels as a whole support the DP when 1) Jesus himself was unjustly sentenced to death, 2) Jesus explicitly repudiates the retaliatory justice of the Mosaic law thorought the Sermon on the Mount ("You have heard it said... but I say to you..."), and 3) Jesus actually stops an execution in John 8? Actually, the Sermon on the Mount is particularly problematic for people who hold that the development of doctrine cannot ever rule out the DP, since Jesus repeatedly rules out acts which were previously permitted under the Law (see Mt. 5:31-39). So, either that which was once permitted can be ruled out by deeper truths of divine revelation (that is, the law of justice can be surpassed by the law of mercy), or Jesus was a liar and a fraud. Development of doctrine does only go in one direction: towards Christ. "You have heard it said... but I say to you..."

      Delete
    2. Thurible, I admire you, bro.

      Delete
    3. If Prof. Feser will allow my extended reply:

      I welcome corrections and better analyses than what I have seen so far. The only thing you say that is new (to me) is Romans 13 is a notoriously difficult text, since some of the things Paul says there are (taken literally) self-evidently false. I not only don’t know what portions “are” false, much less self-evidently false, I don’t even know which portions would tend in that direction. Most of Rom. 13 is advice, which isn’t even in the category of “false” or “true” to begin with. The rest is the self-evidently TRUE declaration that all power comes from God.

      Taking your other points in order:

      to believe too strongly in 1-4 would be an argument against the Christian faith, as it would require that Jesus himself (as well as all the martyred disciples) merely got what was coming to them.

      First, the Fathers and Doctors did “take” what Paul says here both literally and strongly, though they also noted an implication of the passage that limits the APPLICATION of the directive to obey authority: from the very fact that the government’s authority comes from God, that means that when the government tries to give orders that contradict God’s higher law, those orders are not “authoritative” and do not bind. It’s not that Paul’s teaching here is “not to be taken literally”, but that the rule he gives has a qualifier, a limiter, and he himself provides the foundation for that limit.

      Secondly, Pontius Pilate himself gave testimony that Christ had done nothing to warrant punishment, so it simply isn’t true that Christ “got what was coming to him” under Roman law if Paul is understood literally. As for the Christians martyred, quite obviously they were putting into practice the limitation on Paul’s rule, following in the footsteps of John and Peter when they said to the Sanhedrin “it is better to obey God rather than man”, and they were put to death for not obeying “laws” that required them to expressly violate God’s higher law.

      People recoil from that reading, but it's a hard one to escape unless you take Paul merely as saying that the state serves a practical purpose and that it is in the best interest of Christians (as a persecuted minority) not to engage in lawlessness, lest they be struck down by the sword

      The Fathers and Doctors expressly reject this view, they deny that the advice Paul gives is merely of the pragmatic nature of “keep your head down and avoid notice”: St. John Damascene says “For if it be right to requite those that injure us with the opposite, much more is it our duty to obey those that are benefactors to us….If then, whether in punishing, or in honoring, he be a Minister, in avenging virtue's cause, in driving vice away, as God wills, why be captious against him, when he is the cause of so many good doings, and paves the way for yours too? Since there are many who first practised virtue through the fear of God. For there are a duller sort, whom things to come have not such a hold upon as things present. He then who by fear and rewards gives the soul of the majority a preparatory turn towards its becoming more suited for the word of doctrine, is with good reason called the “Minister of God.” Other Fathers say the same.

      Delete
    4. I hope I don't have to explain that the purpose of the thief's dialogue in Luke 23 is to make a theological point about Jesus as an innocent sufferer, not offer a commentary of the liciety of the death penalty

      I agree that the primary focus of what St. Dismas says is the innocence and lordship of Christ. But his declaration demonstrates that he is, in that moment, inspired by the Holy Spirit to see those truths. It is more probable that he is also inspired to see the truth of his own moral state, his sinfulness and his due punishment, and also that Luke chooses to record his declaration on these points because they are true as well as because he said them. It is not necessary to find, from these, that the Romans acted uprightly in their punishing him, to accept Dismas’s testimony as to what he deserves: like with Christ, the Romans could be acting improperly (even if in Dismas’s case he deserves death). It is true that Luke calls the 2 criminals “thieves”, but he also calls them “malefactors”. Mark calls them “rebels”. It is probable they are guilty of more crimes besides theft alone.

      As a whole, the passage does not positively declare expressly that the death penalty is in principle licit, but Luke’s choosing to record Dismas’s words about his own just desserts is an indicator of his (Luke’s) acceptance of Dismas’s affirmation of it, and probable evidence that the whole of what Dismas said was from inspiration.

      It's true that Peter seems to use his power as an apostle to smite Ananias and Sapphira, but the exact causality is unclear, and Luke is deliberately cagey about how the pair perished (they seem to just keel over and die).

      That’s almost, but not quite, what the passage shows. Yes, for Ananias, nothing Peter says seems to clearly point to “you shall die for this sin” and Peter causing it. However, when it comes to Saphira, Peter says ”Behold the feet of them who have buried thy husband are at the door, and they shall carry thee out.” Thus, Peter calls for her death, and the Lord provides it. The Fathers indicate that Peter declared a judgment of death upon her.

      But most importantly, how can we say that the Gospels as a whole support the DP …imply an acceptance of that element of the Law of Moses and there is nothing that expressly overturns that implicit acceptance.

      when 1) Jesus himself was unjustly sentenced to death

      I hope you recognize that this is a complete and absolute nonsequitur! The fact that someone was once wrongly fined $1,000 does NOTHING AT ALL to point for or against the licitness of fines as punishments. No more does it with the DP.

      Jesus explicitly repudiates the retaliatory justice of the Mosaic law thorought the Sermon on the Mount

      There are so many, many ways that Jesus’s revision of the Jews’ understanding’ of the Mosaic Law that are a better analysis than that “Jesus repudiates the retaliatory justice of the Mosaic Law”, that it is impossible to cover them all here. Let it suffice to say just two things: First, when Jesus answers to “what are the greatest of the commandments” and he gives “love God” and “love your neighbor”, he was repeating what was already in the Mosaic Law
      , not creating new law. So the penal parts of the Mosaic Law were never meant to justify the malicious intent of personal, retaliatory revenge. I will address the second aspect after dealing with (3).

      Delete
    5. and 3) Jesus actually stops an execution in John 8
      Arrrggghhhh: because “Jesus stops a (specific) execution” is, again, not even remotely like “Jesus repudiates the DP in the Mosaic Law”. If you ask “HOW did Jesus stop that execution?”, the answer is best captured as “by Jesus following the Mosaic Law”. The whole passage shows the scribes setting a trap and Jesus escaping the trap, and the way Jesus escapes the trap is by following the Law of Moses, showing all the ways that the scribes were violating that law. Briefly: because Jesus did not witness the adultery, UNDER THE LAW he could not be the initiator of the execution. NOWHERE does Jesus declaim against the law that Moses gave for the matter, not even implicitly, nor does he take judgment into his own hands for the matter. Because at every turn Jesus succeeds against the scribes by following the Law, the whole passage amounts to Jesus supporting the Law.

      Jesus also declines to express a general principle about the Mosaic Law after the episode is over: If we were to draw our own general conclusion from the fact that “Jesus stopped the affair” as to what Jesus “seemed” to be suggesting about punishments in the Law, it would probably be that “punishment is wrong”, because she got off without ANY punishment at all. But we don’t think that’s the right conclusion from the fact that Jesus prevented her punishment. There is no room, in the passage, to narrowly draw out “Jesus is against the DP, but he’s OK with other punishments”. None. It’s impossible to extrude such a result.

      Getting back to attempting to utilize the Sermon on the Mount to overturn the penal portion of the Mosaic Law: St. Paul addresses this JUST BEFORE he gives the famous 13:1-4. In Rom. 12, he recaptures exactly what Jesus said in the Sermon, e.g.

      To no man rendering evil for evil. Providing good things, not only in the sight of God, but also in the sight of all men….But if thy enemy be hungry, give him to eat; if he thirst, give him to drink.

      This perfectly conforms to Jesus’ dictum “love your enemies” and “turn the other cheek” to those who strike you, in the Sermon. Yet Paul goes on in verse 19 to CLARIFY the sense of Jesus’s rule:

      19 Revenge not yourselves, my dearly beloved; but give place unto wrath, for it is written: Revenge is mine, I will repay, saith the Lord.

      Thus Paul does 2 things: first, he affirms the retributive principle in penal law, and yet declares that it is not for the individual to impose. It is God’s place to impose it. In many places in the Gospels Jesus affirms God’s divine retribution on sinners, e.g. at the final judgment.

      Then 13:1-4 follows just 3 verses later: The prince or governor is God’s avenging minister. The Fathers and Doctors interpret this, with the Sermon in mind, so as to say that Jesus is NOT overturning the principle of just retribution in the Sermon on the Mount, he is showing that the fact that evildoers are owed just retribution does nothing to relieve YOU of your obligation to love them and do good to them, and Paul shows that the prince, put into authority, is indeed doing good to the evildoers (or those who would be evildoers if there were no civil law) by being God’s avenging minister, as well as doing good to everyone else by promoting virtue. They interpret this and John 7:24 to say that the ruler and judge must rule out of love rather than by personal preference, ambition or desire, and they insist that the ruler being God’s avenging minister does NOT violate this law of love.

      These concerns were all hashed out with tons of analysis over centuries, and the Fathers solved them. Pretending now what they are problems might work for Protestants (who don’t accept reliance on the Fathers), but Catholics can and should rely on the Fathers’ interpretations that unraveled the apparent difficulties.

      Delete
  13. Great post --- for what it is worth, Dr. Feser, as a lay Catholic who has spent very considerable time investigating the faith intellectually, and who has had significant doubts in the past due in part to weak teachers unskilled in apologetics, I think that the sort of attitude had by Fastiggi probably not infrequently contributes to doubts about Catholicism among intellectually-inclined, honest Catholics and non-Catholic seekers alike: Fastiggi is, I take it, a reputable theologian at a Catholic college, but he went on air and pulled what looked (to me) like sophistry: he strawmanned death-penalty advocates as dissenters who like revenge, does not answer Suan's questions plainly (it felt like he really wanted to say the death penalty is intrinsically immoral, and maybe is, but he didn't exactly say it --- felt kinda moat-and-bailey), and adopted what frankly felt like a somewhat manipulative attitude/tone ('you trust the Holy Spirit, don't you? then stop 'dissenting' '). This sort of thing leads at least some --- who knows how many? --- to question the honesty of the Church's intellectual institutions, including people like myself who want to trust them. I don't know if I'm being too harsh on Fastiggi, but people who represent Catholic intellectual life in public should hold themselves to higher standards and avoid cheap debate tactics. [N.B. I consider myself pretty non-partisan regarding the death penalty debate --- I accept whatever the Church teaches, and don't have an agenda beyond consistency with magisterial tradition and natural law.]

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Anon: your instincts about Catholic academia are sound: of the roughly 225 "Catholic" colleges in the US, fewer than 20 provide solidly and reliably Catholic teaching so that you would be justly confident your son or daughter would emerge after 4 years as a life-long committed Catholic. The Jesuit ones are a mess, some apparently declining to even use the term "Catholic" anymore to describe themselves. The common thread of the 200+ is that they proclaim "academic freedom" in the secular manner and have no CLUE that this secular standard ends up in direct defiance of 2 of Jesus's own declarations: "I am the way, the truth, and the life", and "He who hears you [the apostles] hears me".

      Fastiggi teaches at Sacred Heart Seminary in Detroit, which is (a) not NEARLY as bad as the average of US seminaries, and (b) not NEARLY as sound as an average seminary was in 1960 or even 1970. (One of its own (former) professors - one of the good ones - makes negative comments about it.) Until just a few months ago, I would have said it's (still) more good than bad, but the brand new bishop, as one of his first moves, fired 3 of the most orthodox teachers there (and did it flagrantly unfairly), one of them so inoffensively orthodox that it is astonishing that a bishop could have found something in his work that was offensive besides its mere truth. The fact that Fastiggi didn't get the axe, doesn't say something good about him, though I have to admit it also doesn't by itself say anything bad about him as such. It's "negative evidence" which is always very limited in weight.

      Delete
    2. Anon, your point is very valid, and I feel the same.

      I know that it may sound like a 'tin-foil hat' kind of stuff of what I'm about to say, but it seems to me that, every day, more and more of these people infiltrate Catholic circles and distort truth in favor of a more liberal and secularist approach. I'm not sure if they deliberately try to damage tradition for the sake of sounding cool to modern ears, or if there is some other motivation pulling the strings. Either way, it's very clear to me that seminaries nowadays are a factory of intellectualy weak and faithless individuals (such as a father whom I spoke with not long ago, who told me that Adam and Eve were "a myth"), and genuinely interested lay Catholics, like our mensch Ed, are doing more to convert people to Catholicism than the directionless fathers being fabricated at these seminaries.

      To be clear, I think we, as men of goodwill, need to stand up for the Church of Christ and put order in the human body of the Church, which is in a bad shape. We need intelligent, determined, and, most of all, Truth-loving Catholics who are ready to face these dividers among our midst. But I digress.

      Delete
  14. It seems to me that some people who defend Francis's revision and argue against the DP, e.g. Fasttiggi, may be motivated by a fear that the Pope will declare "ex cathedra" that the DP is intrinsically wrong. Thus, in defending the possibility that the DP is intrinsically wrong, they are in some sense laying the groundwork for a defense of the Church should she make such a declaration.

    I am curious Professor Feser, how you would respond to that worry? I imagine you think it is unlikely (maybe even impossible). But if it did happen, would this mean we should be sedevecantists? How should a Catholic respond?

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. It seems to me like there's much more fear on the other side, and much more to lose. I mean, you're the one who just said that the legitimacy of papal authority is (or might be) at stake. If you've convinced yourself that the DP is the clear teaching of the tradition, and that it's a aspect of tradition that cannot change (or at least cannot develop in certain directions), and that if it does change then it brings down all of Catholicism with it (because it falsifies the Church's claim to guard and preserve the deposit of faith)... well, I can't imagine higher stakes. If anyone should be afraid, it's the pro-DP side, because (as another commenter pointed out), this isn't some weird abberation under Francis. You're several popes deep into this shift on the death penalty, and the current pope just reaffirmed the teaching in no uncertain terms.

      Your entire worldview could literally come crashing down tomorrow.

      Delete
    2. > Your entire worldview could literally come crashing down tomorrow.

      That has been a possibility since, oh I don't know, Good Friday. Funnily enough, it hasn't happened yet.

      Delete
    3. "It seems to me like there's much more fear on the other side, and much more to lose."

      Maybe, but I presume your side (to use your own terms) wants to preclude a subsequent development in which this allegedly deeper understanding of the liceity of the death penalty is dropped in favor of an even deeper understanding, in which what was formerly defended and then dropped is now reinstated, so you will have to put some railguards and develop *something* like an equivalent of "clear teaching of the tradition". Or maybe not and you refuse to have any clear teaching at all, but this case merits no response.

      Now "I know this won't surprise or persuade you" (to use your own terms), so I offer it only with the hope that *someone else* may benefit.

      Delete
    4. @English Catholic

      True in one sense, but you can't deny that the specific issue of the DP is a live and active threat to certain understandings of the tradition rather than a vague anxiety (like, say, the possibility that some archeologist might did up Jesus's bones tomorrow).

      @grodrigues

      In some sense, I'm not on either side, not being a Catholic. It doesn't matter to me which side the Church comes down on except to the extent that it makes Christianity as a whole more honest and morally consistent.

      I think you're wrong, however, in assuming that Catholics who oppose the DP (like, not that his opinion matters, the Pope) don't have a coherent theology of development derived from the New Testament or Church history. If your doctrinal teleology is the increase of mercy (which is a higher, not a lower moral standard, as it asks more of Christians and not less), then there's no risk whatsoever of the church sliding back into the logic of retaliation. It matters WHY a moral door is closed, not just that it was closed.

      Delete
    5. The "difficulty" that lies in the question of whether the Church's teachers have taught some specific teaching infallibly via the ordinary and universal magisterium of the college of bishops throughout the world teaching the same doctrine as to be held, or has instead taught it only fallibly, is an unavoidable difficulty for Catholics who take Vatican II's dictum on this seriously. It affects EVERYONE, not just one "side" or the other.

      By the very nature of the case, the manner by which such a teaching "becomes" infallible leaves it open to uncertainty and difficult discernment. There are nuances that inhabit the interior of VII's statement on this, as to both the kind of "universality", and as to the timing / period in which the teaching is taught, that make applying the rule difficult and problematic. The evidence to be used for (or against) is not explained, so we have to search that out elsewhere. That there are people unsure of whether X falls into the class or not should be understood as the unavoidable consequence of the manner by which the infallibility unfolds.

      Nevertheless, not EVERYTHING about the issue is difficult and uncertain. When Pope Pius IX declared Mary's Immaculate Conception as definitive, he indeed surveyed "the Church's" teaching. While he found strong evidence that the Church's prior teaching had been in favor of the doctrine, it wasn't completely favorable in every respect. Yet he felt free to define the doctrine as infallible - and felt the need to do so. The latter was because there arise people who insist the doctrine is uncertain and may be argued against precisely because it has NOT YET been proclaimed definitively in a single infallible act.

      The past evidence in favor of the licitness of DP is incontrovertibly at least as strong as it had been for the Immaculate Conception, but in reality it should be recognized as MUCH stronger.

      There are those who want to urge the POV that a Catholic "shouldn't" hold to a doctrine as "definitive" and "infallible" unless it has been formally defined by a Pope speaking ex cathedra or by a Council. But this would render completely ineffectual Vatican II's teaching about the class of infallible teachings that became so through the concordance of the world's bishops throughout the world teaching it. One could put it that Pius IX (and Pius XII), in defining anew ancient doctrines on Mary were confirming these doctrines because of the hardness of heart of those who FAILED to accept them on the basis of the universal Church's teaching them, and needed proof beyond what obediential faith would demand, and who called into doubt by erroneous claims what should have been accepted ALREADY because of what the bishops have taught.

      Giving effect to the Vatican II, and looking to Pius IX's and Pius XII's examples of confirming doctrines that had already been taught so universally, it seems that a person is justified in faith to credit the ancient and perennial doctrine of the Church on the licitness of the DP as having already been taught infallibly.

      I welcome Leo or ANY pope speaking ex cathedra on this in a clear and unambiguous way; I did the same with Francis. I have no doubt that if they do so, they will comport with the whole body of the Church's teaching. If they decline to do so, and then say things that THEY KNOW don't look conformable to the ancient doctrine, then they seem by that very fact to be OK with people looking at these saying askance and asking "but how does that comport with the prior teaching". And if they decline to bother answering that question, they thereby indicate they DON'T require obediential submission to such sayings.

      Delete
  15. The image of the executioner is apropos. Let's go back to public hangings. The last public hanging was in Kentucky in 1936.

    ReplyDelete
  16. I agree with almost everything Prof. Edward Feser writes about the death penalty. However, I am concerned about one aspect of this issue. Namely, according to traditional Catholic theology, while it may be possible to suspend one's internal assent to the content of the ordinary Magisterium of the Church (after careful examination of the matter), one should not engage in public polemics with such teaching.
    What do you think about this, Professor?

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Respectful criticism can be public, as Aquinas taught and as the Church acknowledges. Aquinas writes:

      "If the faith were endangered, a subject ought to rebuke his prelate even publicly. Hence Paul, who was Peter's subject, rebuked him in public, on account of the imminent danger of scandal concerning faith, and, as the gloss of Augustine says on Galatians 2:11, 'Peter gave an example to superiors, that if at any time they should happen to stray from the straight path, they should not disdain to be reproved by their subjects.'" (Summa Theologiae II-II.33.4)

      I discuss this and other relevant texts in two blog posts:

      https://edwardfeser.blogspot.com/2018/05/the-church-permits-criticism-of-popes_20.html

      https://edwardfeser.blogspot.com/2022/08/aquinas-on-st-pauls-correction-of-st.html

      Delete

    2. However, the document of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Donum Veritatis, teaches in point 30 that a theologian who suspends his internal assent to a given act of the ordinary Magisterium:

      "In cases like these, the theologian should avoid turning to the "mass media", but have recourse to the responsible authority, for it is not by seeking to exert the pressure of public opinion that one contributes to the clarification of doctrinal issues and renders servite to the truth. "
      The opinion of St. Thomas Aquinas cited by you does not necessarily refer to justifying public polemics with the acts of the official teaching of the Church. Moreover, the biblical case referred to here by Thomas Aquinas did not concern the public and official teaching of St. Peter the Apostle: it concerned his actions (the implications of which could lead to errors against the faith).

      By the way, what do you think of the view of some prominent Catholic theologians who claim that even in the non-infallible part of the Magisterium there can be no errors that would seriously harm faith and morality?

      Delete
    3. Regarding disagreement with the prudential teaching that the death penalty is inadmissible in today’s circumstances, I think that Ed’s appeal to ‘Donum Veritatis’ faces several obstacles.

      As a preliminary – there’s no issue reaffirming past magisterial teachings that capital punishment is not intrinsically evil. The recent popes haven’t contradicted this, and indeed the magisterium has explicitly stated that the new formulation in the Catechism ‘is not in contradiction with the prior teachings of the magisterium’ (‘Letter to Bishops Regarding the New Revision’ 8).

      However, regarding the prudential teaching, and its supposedly non-binding nature:

      1. An appeal to St Thomas Aquinas’ statement ‘that if the faith were endangered, a subject ought to rebuke his prelate even publicly’ becomes more problematic, since this prudential teaching can hardly be claimed to be in itself an imminent and obvious danger to the faith.

      2. It’s clear from ‘Donum Veritatis’ that the Magisterium can assert prudential judgments which have some degree of binding force. Thus it states: ‘the Magisterium can intervene in questions under discussion which involve, in addition to solid principles, certain contingent and conjectural elements’ (24). The recent prudential judgments on the death penalty are not presented as merely the private theological opinions of Pope Francis or Pope John Paul.

      Ed compares prudential judgment on the death penalty with judgments on whether a war is just, referring to the Catechism’s teaching that ‘the evaluation of these conditions for moral legitimacy [of a war] belongs to the prudential judgment of those who have responsibility for the common good.’ (2309)

      The meaning there, I suggest, is in reference to individual wars, and denying that this prudential judgment of their justice is the role of individual citizens or soldiers. A parallel might be, in social circumstances where there was no overall inadmissibility of the death penalty, that the decision on which specific types of crime and which individual cases be subject to the death penalty lies with civil authorities (legislators and judges), not private citizens.

      However, the question of Church authority is not under consideration there, as if on a par with private citizens. These matters have relevance to morality and salvation, so the Church does have divine guidance and therefore competence – not with respect to individual criminals, or specific wars, but with broader questions of how to interpret the timeless principles in today’s world.

      Delete
    4. 3. ‘Donum Veritatis’, in speaking about the possibility of legitimate divergence from non-irreformable teachings, is speaking about the leeway given to theologians (and maybe even, only those who receive ‘the canonical mission or the mandate to teach…making the profession of faith, and taking the oath of fidelity’ (22)). It says nothing about this leeway being given to the faithful in general. So if we’re not theologians, we can’t assume this leeway for ourselves simply based on ‘Donum Veritatis’; and even if we are theologians, we shouldn’t encourage non-theologians to assume that leeway for themselves on such basis.

      4. ‘Even if the doctrine of the faith is not in question, the theologian will not present his own opinions or divergent hypotheses as though they were non-arguable conclusions.’ (‘Donum Veritatis’ 27). However, some of the statements by various commenters of disagreement with this prudential judgment of the Magisterium are indeed presented ‘as though they were non-arguable conclusions’ - maybe even to the extent of suggesting that anyone who defends the magisterial teaching must surely be, not just wrong, but intellectually dishonest.

      5. ‘The theologian will refrain from giving untimely public expression to [his own opinions or divergent hypotheses]’ (‘Donum Veritatis’ 27). Granted, this suggests or implies that there can be legitimate public expression of ‘divergent hypotheses’ as long as that expression is not ‘untimely’. But the implication is that this would be the exception rather than the norm.

      It may be worthwhile discussing what conditions might need to apply for public expression not to be ‘untimely’; and to give hypothetical examples of ‘untimely’ and ‘timely’ expressions. There could be a temptation for a theologian to consider any public expression timely, based merely on his view that his opinion is true and speaking the truth is always beneficial. But that position would render this statement of ‘Donum Veritatis’ otiose.

      6. And it is worth mentioning, finally, the following condition of ‘Donum Veritatis’ regarding ‘the case of the theologian who might have serious difficulties, for reasons which appear to him well-founded, in accepting a non-irreformable magisterial teaching. Such a disagreement could not be justified if it were based solely upon the fact that the validity of the given teaching is not evident or upon the opinion that the opposite position would be the more probable.’ (28)

      Delete
    5. "There could be a temptation for a theologian to consider any public expression timely, based merely on his view that his opinion is true and speaking the truth is always beneficial. But that position would render this statement of ‘Donum Veritatis’ otiose."
      Well, yes: Stupid people (including stupid theologians) are subject to being tempted by stupid ideas. (Stupid is as stupid does.)
      But also: Otiose bromides (like the one cited from DV 27) don't need to be 'rendered' otiose.

      Delete
    6. I have a question about the application of DV: it speaks of the requirement to give "religious submission" to the reformable teachings of the Church's magisterial teachers. But at least traditionally, the reformable teachings are divided into 3 or perhaps more categories: (1) those that are teachings of the bishops of a sort that COULD (eventually) become irreformable teachings that are taught infallibly, and are held forth by the bishops asserting them as true and to be held. Then (2) there are the prudential judgments of the teachers, e.g. taking general principles and applying them to specific situations with lots and lots of complexifying details: these are generally not thought to be of such a character as that they could ever become irreformable infallible teachings, because, e.g., it is impossible to be wholly certain of all the circumstantial details that go into the prudential judgment. As a result they are not put forward (by GOOD teachers) in a manner that appears to demand religious submission of mind and will. And finally, there are teachings by the bishops that are proposed for the faithful: suggestions, trial balloons, pious thoughts, speculative theories, maybes and possibles and explorations. They are not put forth (by good teachers) in the expectation of religious submission, but for pious attention.

      The problem is that it is rare - nay, it is virtually unheard of in these days - that bishops take the trouble to distinguish these categories when they teach. At best, they expect the reader or hearer to "work it out" by context. At worst, they not only don't themselves know which category they intend, they aren't even AWARE of the distinctions between the categories and are unable to teach in a manner that respects them. At least this: it is habitual among bishops NOT to be cautious in teaching things that really belong in the 3rd category without making an effort to clarify that they belong in the 3rd category.

      The issue comes to a head in DV, because if a bishop teaches something that has the appearance of being in the 1st category but is really just a proposal or an informal idea, the theologian (or anyone else) shouldn't be required to submit in the form of religious submission.

      For example, in Evangelium Vitae, John Paul for the first time (in papal circles) floated the idea that the DP must be restricted to cases where safety cannot otherwise be secured. As mentioned above, he did not argue for this new position. It is quite extraordinary to present a NEW teaching, WITHOUT argument or even clarification, as if it now requires religious submission. In this case, JPII in the next paragraph says "In any event", a phrase used to indicate that the prior point is uncertain, or at least that some disagreement with it is anticipated and acceptable. Arguably, JPII, knowing that his thesis was not a simple and direct conclusion from the perennial teaching, intended to leave room for disagreement, he was putting it forward as a proposal, a trial balloon, a theory.

      If so, I put it that because religious submission is not required, a theologian's disagreement is NOT in violation of anything in DV. And when he put it in the Catechism, that didn't change the level. Cardinal Schönborn said that the items in the Catechism carried the authority of the other sources from which they were drawn. If it was a proposal in EV, it was a proposal in the Catechism.

      If Francis simply parked his new phrasing for 2267 by merely assuming JPII's proposal, without any analysis or any separate assertion that it is taught more authoritatively, does it become a category (1) teaching? In this case, the new 2267 was only a papal address to the Pontifical Council for the Promotion of the New Evangelization: Hardly a hard doctrinal setting, you don't expect the presentation of a new moral doctrine, requiring religious assent, in a speech to evangelists.

      Delete
    7. When we get to Dignitas Infinita, it is plausible that here we finally get a statement that might amount to a teaching whose form represents an expectation of religious assent. But it again offers no foundation nor any effort at all to address the obvious tension with the perennial teaching, to which the faithful are STILL required to give religious submission. I don't see how attention to DV solves this. Indeed, the theologian who takes seriously DV's urging "to understand this teaching in its contents, arguments, and purposes" will be frustrated because no arguments are offered. And when cardinals submit dubia which go unanswered, he has no reasonable hope for a different result for his own questions. Is he NOT permitted to think that if the Church neither offers arguments, nor explanations addressed to the tension, nor responds to questions, it is not INTENDING to teach these as "to be held, but is merely offering pious ideas, conjectures, and theories.

      Delete
    8. And since stupid people and stupid theologians do exist, it is unfortunately often necessary or at least useful to explicitly counteract stupid ideas.

      But the deficient idea that 'speaking the truth is always beneficial' (at least in matters of theory such as theology and philosophy, rather than e.g. revealing personal or state secrets), I think is not uncommon as a practical rule that people assume and follow.

      But if, as we agree, this practical rule is not correct, at least not as an absolute, then on what alternative grounds do you consider the statement of DV 27 otiose, rather than being a useful caution to theologians?

      In the absence of such alternative grounds, your post seems liable to the interpretation, 'You would have to be stupid to believe this idea that would make DV 27 otiose; and yes, DV 27 is otiose because this idea is true.'

      Delete
    9. is speaking about the leeway given to theologians (and maybe even, only those who receive ‘the canonical mission or the mandate to teach…making the profession of faith, and taking the oath of fidelity’ (22)). It says nothing about this leeway being given to the faithful in general. So if we’re not theologians, we can’t assume this leeway for ourselves simply based on ‘Donum Veritatis’; and even if we are theologians, we shouldn’t encourage non-theologians to assume that leeway for themselves on such basis.

      Interestingly, while Donum Veritatis notes that theologians MAY receive a canonical mission or mandate to teach, it speaks generically of theologians (even those not so given a mandatum) and even the importance of the work of theology, which would seem to include ALL who study theology, or works of theology, even if not getting a degree. All who study it should do so in union with the Magisterium, not just theologians.

      The problem is that ANY Catholic who is going to read something like Dignitas Infinita without confusion and taking only what is meant to be asserted without admixture of error must needs be educated to some extent in theology. If he isn't a theologian, he better at least have a good theology background. But if he has that background, he probably will see the tension created by the document as compared to the perennial teaching. It doesn't take having a mandatum or a theology degree to be thrust into the difficulty of assenting to the perennial teaching AND the position indicated in DI. So, it cannot be special to being a theologian to have proper ways of handling the difficulty. While it might sound high and noble to say "well, you don't speak out loud about the problem", but how else will such a person contend with the difficulty? Go to his bishop? Many of them decline to deal with it. Go to the Vatican? Be real: if the Vatican won't answer cardinals who raise the issue, they aren't going to answer when a lay person asks. Obviously, if a layman who isn't a theologian has enough education to see the difficulty then he NEEDS enough "leeway" to solve it. I don't see how anything in "granted" in DV is in principle limited to theologians.

      Delete
    10. @ Tony October 16, 2025 at 1:48 PM

      I agree that there can be different levels/categories of teaching intention within the one magisterial document. (I don’t think, historically speaking, that it’s particularly unusual for these not to be clearly delineated in the document – looking for example at pre-conciliar encyclicals. It’s always been left largely to theologians to work out after the fact.)

      Regarding the argumentation for the teaching, or lack thereof – first, we’re talking here about the prudential teaching that the death penalty is inadmissible in the present day. (From everything that’s been said by Ed and others, including by myself earlier in the comments, I think we can take it as an untenable interpretation that the Magisterium is now asserting the death penalty to be intrinsically evil. In any event, everything I’ve said in this thread in connection with DV assumes that as a given.)

      Looking across the teachings of John Paul II and Francis, I wouldn’t say there’s no argument at all for the prudential teaching, even if it’s only given in rudimentary form. And I’d say that it’s fairly normal for magisterial documents (historically and currently) to only provide the rudiments of argumentation. DV 34 mentions the ‘hermeneutical rule…that Magisterial teaching, by virtue of divine assistance, has a validity beyond its argumentation, which may derive at times from a particular theology.’ So I think the fact of a document only providing rudimentary argumentation doesn’t establish that there is no intention to require religious submission.

      Many magisterial assertions and documents provide little or no argumentation or explanation. (Examples off the top of my head – the 1968 ‘Credo of the People of God’. Or, from 1854 (Singulari Quadam), the Magisterium started putting forward the teaching that salvation was not impossible even for someone who was not formally a member of the Catholic Church; an extended magisterial explanation of how this fitted in with past teachings wasn’t really given until the 1949 ‘Letter of the Holy Office to the Archbishop of Boston’.)

      But anyway, the key point as to whether a teaching is binding or not is the intention of the particular pope giving the teaching. We see this in the primary source regarding the Ordinary Magisterium of the Pope, which is from Vatican II: ‘This religious submission of the will and intellect must be shown in a special way to the authentic Magisterium of the Roman Pontiff, even when he is not speaking ex cathedra; that is, it must be shown in such a way that his supreme Magisterium is acknowledged with reverence, and that the judgements made by him are sincerely adhered to, according to his manifest mind and will, which is made known principally either from the character of the documents, from his frequent repetition of the same doctrine, or from his manner of speaking.’ (Lumen Gentium 25)

      Leaving aside Pope John Paul, it seems implausible in regard to Pope Francis to say that he had no intention for his teaching on the inadmissibility of the death penalty to have any binding force – both ‘from his frequent repetition of the same doctrine’ and ‘from his manner of speaking.’ (Beyond the Catechism revision, Dignitas Infinita, and papal speeches, I’d also mention the CDF ‘Letter to Bishops’ that accompanied the Catechism revision, formally approved by Francis.) I think he made his ‘mind and will’ quite manifest, that he was not simply putting forward 'pious ideas, conjectures and theories'.

      Delete
    11. Ben, if you can figure out a cure for human stupidity, then you'll deserve the Nobel peace prize ahead of Trump.
      As for the passage from DV 27, it says that theologians should express their views in a timely way; that is, they should express their views only when they should express their views. Now maybe I'm the stupid one here, but it seems to me that one must be exceptionally stupid not to see that such advice is entirely idle. It isn't the least bit helpful for a stupid person, or a non-stupid one. St Paul is considerably clearer in his advice: "Preach the word, insist on it, timely or untimely." (2Tm 6) Unfortunately, Paul's advice seems to be in tension with that of DV 27 -- except that, in any case, DV 27 would seem not obviously to apply in the present case, where the theologian does not take himself to be presenting 'his own opinion' as such, but rather the traditional and magisterial teaching of sacred scripture and Holy Mother Church.

      Delete
    12. Tony, I agree with your observations here. I would say that the 'usual' reading of the requirement of 'religious submission' to fallible (i.e., possibly false) teachings flatly does violence to human conscience and reason. It seems necessary to emphasize the qualifier 'religious' here, in order to emphasize that what is enjoined cannot be just human submission to fallible human teaching, but properly religious submission, that is, submission that is objectively oriented by justice towards God, the one and only perfectly just judge of us all, including popes. Submission to the teachings of a manifestly ignorant, lazy, erroneous prelate, just because he is a prelate, should hardly count as genuinely 'religious.' And if it does, then such 'religion' is worthless.

      Delete
    13. @Tony October 16, 2025 at 4:12 PM

      I mentioned as something tentative, the possibility of the leeway to withhold assent being limited to ‘those who receive the canonical mission or the mandate to teach…making the profession of faith, and taking the oath of fidelity’; I didn’t find DV clear on this point. But without this, it seems unclear who counts as a theologian.

      The general duty of religious assent for all Catholics is set forth clearly in Vatican II, as well as in pre-conciliar teachings, with no mention of exceptions (see DS 2880, DS 3408, DS 3503); so the onus of proof is on someone who wants to claim exemption. And so it becomes relevant to know exactly who can avail themselves of the exception that is set forth in DV.

      My original comment didn’t rule out in principle that an exception might extend beyond theologians - I limited myself to saying that based on DV alone, an exception for theologians was all that could be established. The text of DV never goes beyond that; and that limitation to theologians reflects what I believe was the pre-conciliar understanding. (See Ott, ‘Fundamentals of Catholic Dogma’ (1952), p. 11: ‘By way of exception, the obligation of inner assent may cease if a competent expert, after a renewed scientific investigation of all grounds, arrives at the positive conviction that the decision rests on an error.’ I’ve read that at Vatican II, it was suggested that an exception of this nature be written into Lumen Gentium 25; but this was considered unnecessary, since the possibility of this rare exception was already sufficiently known to theologians.)

      As I mention in my previous comment, I’m focussing on the duty of assent to the prudential teaching on current inadmissibility of the death penalty, taking as a given that the issue of apparent flat contradiction between past and present teaching has already been resolved.

      But it’s worth adding, the mere fact of tensions between teachings doesn’t magically create a new exemption from the duty of assent. Dealing with tensions, even apparent contradictions, between different teachings is a constant for anyone trying to grapple with Christian faith – going back to when Christ demanded faith from his hearers in his divine Sonship, without first anxiously explaining to them how this was compatible with the divine unity. The Magisterium, following his example, has not limited itself to giving out teachings that are all explained and justified in advance. Working it out is primarily the job of the theologians.

      Delete
    14. "The Magisterium, following his example, has not limited itself to giving out teachings that are all explained and justified in advance. Working it out is primarily the job of the theologians."
      Ben, for the record, I repudiate in the strongest terms your belief in an atheological Magisterium, which has no need of theological (or otherwise) justifications for its fallible prudential teachings. (Like, seriously, mon?!). Christ never demanded religious assent to stuff just because he said so. That is an absurdly anachronistic imposture and misrepresentation of the gospels. Still less did he ever demand religious submission of mind and heart to false teachings. He came into this world to bear witness to the truth.
      Your approach is very badly skewed towards the postivistic. I'm curious if you give any consideration to principles of natural justice? You seem happy to adopt principles willy-nilly based only on tenuous interpretations of positivistic teachings and to completely disregard natural justice, as if you have a purely nominalistic conception of natural justice.

      Delete
    15. I’m focussing on the duty of assent to the prudential teaching on current inadmissibility of the death penalty,

      Ben, there are plenty of authors, including theologians in favor of the new teaching, who are convinced that the new teaching in 2267 and DI is not a prudential judgment, but one of principle. So...it appears to be IN DOUBT as to whether it is prudential or not. But it is quite probable that the actual content to which we are required to give assent DEPENDS CLOSELY on the same details that determine whether it is a prudential judgment or not. Hence, more likely than not, the precise content to which assent is required is in doubt. As David points out, the requirement to assent is problematic when the proposition to be assented to is unclear in meaning. Many theologians admit that "inadmissible" is unclear in meaning, whether they approve or disapprove of the new teaching.

      taking as a given that the issue of apparent flat contradiction between past and present teaching has already been resolved.

      I'm glad to year you think this is a given, but I assure you that in other circles it is not accepted. I have seen in print various writers explicitly declare that the two are in flatly in contradiction, and that we are bound to accept what Francis said, and ignore facile and rather obviously fictitious side assertions by the Vatican that "there's no contradiction".

      Delete
    16. But anyway, the key point as to whether a teaching is binding or not is the intention of the particular pope giving the teaching...

      OK, so you seem to be indicating that you think the kind of submission meant by "religious submission of mind and will" applies even to prudential judgments by which the pope or bishop applies general principles to particular circumstances. I don't think is the usual way of reading the relevant passages of DV. #23 sets forth 3 categories of doctrinal teaching, in 3 paragraphs, each demanding a different sort of asset: the 1st for an assent of faith for a teaching divinely revealed. The 2nd kind required that they be "firmly accepted and held". The third is for a class of non-definitive teachings, which are to be accepted under "religious submission of will and intellect," further described with “obedience to the faith.”

      # 24 then goes on to discuss yet another kind of teaching: in the 1st par., one that bears even less of the imprint of divine guidance than the 3rd mentioned in #23: interventions which involve “solid principles” as well as “certain contingent and conjectural elements”. It is implausible that the kind of assent required is the same kind. It certainly doesn’t say so. By starting with “Finally,…” it clearly makes a break from the three kinds in #23.

      The 2nd par. indicates that here the theologian’s willingness should be to “submit loyally”, not using “religious submission” nor a similar phrase. The second sentence of the 1st par. provides an indication of why: only the FUTURE will determine what is necessary and what is contingent.

      The 3rd par. In #24 identifies the category "interventions of the prudential order", which clearly are not in any of the three in #23; it provides for an even larger scope of possible problems in such magisterial teachings than those mentioned in the 1st par., and which provides an even larger scope for the theologian's qualified assent. The bulwark indicated against a deficiency of assent is that the theologian must not conclude that the Church could be habitually mistaken in its prudential judgments, or does not enjoy divine assistance in the integral exercise of its mission. Those are quite low bars, and hardly any serious Catholic thinker in the DP debate is likely to run anywhere near that boundary.

      Given the structure of the ideas and how they are laid out, it is patently implausible that #24 (all three paragraphs) is meant to describe classes that, like the 3rd in #23, require religious submission of mind and will. It is ambiguous whether the 2nd par. means to describe a different category than those in the 1st and 3rd, or whether the 1st and 3rd are meant to be different from each other. But either answer for those questions still leaves #24 set apart from #23. The phrase “per se not irreformable” is readily and aptly understood to cover those kinds of propositions the Church has held to be of such a character that they can’t be taught infallibly, because they’re of the wrong sort, and it is traditionally true that she has applied this sense also to those described in the 3rd par., i.e. interventions in the prudential order, about which the protection of the Holy Spirit is of a lesser kind: that the Church will not habitually err and will not fail her integral mission. So, either the 2nd par. sets forth a standard of “submissive loyalty” and that standard also covers the class in the 3rd. par., or the class in the 3rd par. has an even lower standard, neither option arising to “religious submission.”

      I believe that Card. Ratzinger confirmed this POV expressly when he intervened in the letter to Card. McCarrick explaining that unlike with abortion, a Catholic who held to a disagreement with JPII on the prudential judgment on DP is not by that fact in contravention of his obligation to submit to the Church’s teaching.

      Delete

    17. @ David McPike, October 17, 2025 at 5:16 PM

      David - going back to the text of DV 27, the sentence prior to the one we’ve been discussing points to a substantive answer to the question of when public expression of ‘divergent hypotheses’ would be ‘untimely’. The passage states: ‘Respect for the truth as well as for the People of God requires this discretion (cf. Rom 14:1-15; 1 Cor 8; 10:23-33)’. The scripture references are key (which I admit I hadn’t looked up before). They’re all about not scandalizing the weak. Doing something that for me is not in itself a sin, might lead another person to do something that is a sin for them.

      So how might this apply to the case at hand? I know you don’t agree with my whole approach to ‘religious submission’; but suppose for the sake of argument that it’s correct that only theologians are granted a right to withhold assent from non-infallible teachings, whereas non-theologians are granted no such right (as it seems was at least the pre-Vatican II understanding, and is arguably that of DV).

      If a theologian then publicly presents arguments for the incorrectness of a magisterial teaching, his arguments, right or wrong, would tend to lead the non-theologians in the direction of also disagreeing with the magisterial statement – which for them would be a sin. It would obviously be wrong for the theologian to directly intend their sin; but even to permit the risk of it as an unintended side effect of his publicizing his arguments, there would need to be a sufficient countervailing benefit.

      Or even if non-theologians do also have a right of withholding assent, experience shows that once they avail themselves of this in a limited case, many do not have the intellectual discipline to keep it within the strict limits permitted (as even theologians are obliged to do). For example, from diverging from Pope Francis’ official teaching on two or three points, they quickly scorn his whole magisterium. (It is beside the point how much Francis himself was to blame for this reaction.)

      Logically, it need not be a ‘slippery slope’, but with our human nature, de facto it often becomes one. So in view of this, a theologian needs to be cautious not to set people in the first place on the path towards a possible habit of dissent – again, unless there is a sufficient countervailing benefit foreseen, to justify the risk.

      Finally, supposing for the sake of argument that there are a few incorrect magisterial statements current that need correction, and that there are a few valid corrections from theologians publicly out there. Even so, in the vast majority of cases, magisterial teachings are correct and the ‘divergent hypotheses’ put out there by theologians are simply wrong. The faithful who lack theological expertise have a certain right to be protected from the latter. This justifies a general rule of conduct of not putting divergent hypotheses out there for the general public at all - leaving aside clearly enunciated exceptional circumstances that would justify the risk.

      Delete

    18. @ David McPike, October 17, 2025 at 5:16 PM

      “Ben, for the record, I repudiate in the strongest terms your belief in an atheological Magisterium, which has no need of theological (or otherwise) justifications for its fallible prudential teachings.”

      David, I think you’ve constructed this ‘belief’ of mine out of a fairly slim acquaintance with my theology! I certainly hold to the need for theological justifications, whether provided by the Magisterium or theologians - though observing that faith is not directly built upon rational justification.

      But my previous statements in this regard aren’t really ‘beliefs’ - rather, historical observations that an atheist could equally make: in particular, that the Magisterium has frequently omitted providing theological justifications from its pronouncements. (See for example, its numerous extended lists of condemned propositions, e.g. of Luther (DS 1452-92); or laxism (DS 2021-65, 2101-67); or Jansenism (DS 2400-2502); or modernism (DS 3401-66). Various of these are only ‘prudential’, if that is a relevant factor.)

      Christ himself clearly did not provide a substantial theology of the Trinity or the Incarnation to set the minds of his hearers at rest about whether his divine claims contradicted Jewish faith in the One God. Another famous example is his Bread of Life discourse, (Jn 6:48-71) where he does expect belief simply based on his own word. He gives no explanation of how what he says is possible. There were ‘justifications’ for those willing to accept them, but these are extrinsic to the teaching itself: his own person, the wisdom of his previous teachings, his miracles, the inner testimony of the Holy Spirit.

      I’m not sure what you’re getting at with regard to the statements on ‘natural justice’. If your concern is that I (or the Magisterium) are expecting people to believe things without regard to truth, the answer lies in the virtue of faith, which is founded on God the First Truth. Our ‘religious submission’ ‘though distinct from the assent of faith, is nonetheless an extension of it’. (Catechism 892) These teachings are guided by the Holy Spirit, even if not so comprehensively as to exclude all possibility of error. That is the religious motive of our assent.

      I do champion the power and necessity of reason, and the motives of credibility; but I am not a rationalist. (Cf. Vatican I, Dei Filius)

      Delete

    19. @Tony, October 18, 2025 at 4:22 PM

      Tony, even if we grant for the sake of argument that the precise meaning of the teaching is not clear in every aspect, it doesn’t mean that we don’t know the intended meaning at all, and are therefore released from any duty of assenting to it. Whatever the ‘inadmissibility’ of the death penalty means, it is sufficiently clear that in the intention of Pope Francis, it excludes supporting the current practice of capital punishment - so we need at least to assent to that aspect.

      Authors who say that we are bound to accept what Francis has taught, but who claim a contradiction between the past and present teachings, by that very fact are denying Francis’ own teaching (or at least, the teaching of the CDF ‘Letter to Bishops’ - formally approved by Francis and therefore participating in his Magisterium) - that the new formulation in the Catechism ‘is not in contradiction with the prior teachings of the Magisterium’ (8). This is a magisterial statement they are going against, not a mere ‘side assertion by the Vatican’ such as from the Press Office.

      It is a ridiculous position on the part of such authors, because it is itself an act of dissent from Francis. And if they say the assertion of non-contradiction is insincere, they are openly calling him a liar for approving the document - so they can hardly position themselves as his supporters.

      Delete

    20. @Tony, October 18, 2025 at 4:30 PM

      Tony, a later document of the CDF – its 1998 ‘Doctrinal Commentary on the Concluding Formula of the Professio Fidei’ - clearly includes prudential teachings under the category of those requiring religious submission:

      ‘10. The third proposition of the Professio fidei states: “Moreover, I adhere with religious submission of will and intellect to the teachings which either the Roman Pontiff or the College of Bishops enunciate when they exercise their authentic Magisterium, even if they do not intend to proclaim these teachings by a definitive act.” To this paragraph belong all those teachings on faith and morals - presented as true or at least as sure, even if they have not been defined with a solemn judgment or proposed as definitive by the ordinary and universal Magisterium. Such teachings are, however, an authentic expression of the ordinary Magisterium of the Roman Pontiff or of the College of Bishops and therefore require religious submission of will and intellect. (Cf. Vatican II, Lumen Gentium, 25; CDF Donum Veritatis, 23) They are set forth in order to arrive at a deeper understanding of revelation, or to recall the conformity of a teaching with the truths of faith, or lastly to warn against ideas incompatible with these truths or against dangerous opinions that can lead to error. (Cf. CDF Donum Veritatis, 23 & 24) A proposition contrary to these doctrines can be qualified as erroneous or, in the case of teachings of the prudential order, as rash or dangerous and therefore “tuto doceri non potest”. (Cf. Code of Canon Law, can. 752)’

      ‘11. ‘…As examples of doctrines belonging to the third paragraph, one can point in general to teachings set forth by the authentic ordinary Magisterium in a non-definitive way, which require degrees of adherence differentiated according to the mind and the will manifested; this is shown especially by the nature of the documents, by the frequent repetition of the same doctrine, or by the tenor of the verbal expression.’ (Cf. Vatican II, Lumen Gentium, 25; CDF Donum Veritatis, 17, 23 & 24)’

      As you can see, the ‘Doctrinal Commentary’, expounding the 'religious submission of will and intellect', speaks of teachings ‘presented as true or at least as sure’, and of ‘teachings of the prudential order.’ The references given are in the original - both DV 23 and 24 are referenced.

      True, the teachings ‘require degrees of adherence differentiated according to the mind and will manifested’. This allows for different degrees of response to teachings falling under DV 23 and DV 24 respectively. But both are included by the ‘Doctrinal Commentary’ under the general category of ‘religious submission of will and intellect’.

      Regarding Cardinal Ratzinger’s Letter to Cardinal McCarrick – this was after Pope John Paul’s teaching, but before Pope Francis’. So a little more wiggle room existed at that stage – Pope John Paul’s ‘very rare, if not practically non-existent’ vs. Pope Francis’ ‘inadmissible’.

      But also, even now the teaching on the death penalty is not on the same level as the teaching on abortion and euthanasia, both of which are taught to be intrinsically evil. The grave sinfulness of these latter is infallibly taught by the ordinary and universal magisterium, so anyone denying them is ‘no longer in full communion with the Catholic Church’ (CDF Doctrinal Commentary 6; cf. ‘Evangelium Vitae’ 62; 65; ‘Doctrinal Commentary’ 11; ‘Samaritanus Bonus’ (2020), footnote 38)

      Delete
  17. That the death penalty is not intrinsically wrong is clear from both natural law and from the Hebrew Scriptures. One does not need to consult the teachings of any denomination to know that the death penalty is not intrinsically wrong.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Correct. The DP not intrinsically wrong in theory. It is that the application of it today is wrong.

      Delete
  18. It seems that John Paul II's teaching ("if this is the only possible way of effectively defending human lives against the unjust aggressor") does depart in some way from the traditional understanding. That is to say, John Paul II collapses Church teaching on the death penalty to the case of defense, and assimilates the state's power in this regard to the right of the individual to use force to defend himself. But the individual does NOT have the authority to will the death of an aggressor as such, merely the right to use NECESSARY force to defend himself (which could POTENTIALLY extend as far as lethal force; but death itself is not willed as a means or an end). But the state, which is God's minister (cf. Romans 13) really DOES have the authority to will the death of a malefactor AS A PUNISHMENT, and not merely to use lethal force when necessary to defend society. It is true that John Paul II's teaching (unlike that of Francis) cannot even possibly be read as suggesting that the death penalty is intrinsically immoral, but he does sidestep the traditional affirmation of capital punishment precisely as retributive justice. The teaching of John Paul II includes a traditional element (the recognition in principle of the moral liceity of the death penalty) and a novel element (collapsing the death penalty into self defense). One could argue that Francis's teaching IS in fact a "development" -- but not a development of traditional Catholic teaching; rather a development OF JOHN PAUL II'S TEACHING -- that is, a development of the problematic, novel part of that teaching that then abandons the traditional element it had retained. Francis's teaching is DEEPLY problematic, but I think we need to acknowledge that John Paul II's teaching is also problematic in its own way. His teaching sets the stage for Francis's errors.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Well, Peter, you certainly put Pope St. John Paul II in his place.

      Delete
  19. The teaching of John Paul II includes a traditional element (the recognition in principle of the moral liceity of the death penalty) and a novel element (collapsing the death penalty into self defense).

    I think you are right, and it's not merely problematic: JPII does the collapsing without even a pretense at either an argument or an explanatory comment: first he proclaims the traditional teaching that the primary purpose of punishment is the retributive end. In his 1995 encyclical Evangelium Vitae he moves forward by simply switching the game board by then declaring that "the context" for the death penalty is defense / safety. Nowhere does he provide an explanation for that switch, not even a hypothesis or suggestion. And nowhere does he even hint that this "context" might lie in tension with the primary end of punishment, which is the state's right and duty to pursue. JPII is a masterful thinker, and knows how to make a careful argument - which he demonstrates thoroughly in things like Veritatis Splendor. The fact that he doesn't even ATTEMPT it here seems significant. It is my opinion that the entire treatment under "the context" of defense / safety more plausible as representing his floating an idea, and for that reason it should not be treated as a magisterial provision but as a theologian's speculation. He even follows it in EV with "In any event...", as if to suggest that the prior discussion is tentative or at least not certain.

    ReplyDelete
  20. I support the death penalty. So, if Pope Leo XIV condemns it, I wish he would answer three questions. First, if execution is always immoral, why did Our Blessed Lord let the two thieves die on their crosses when he could have saved their lives? Second, what penalty would the Holy Father give to lifers who murder prison guards? Third, has the Church decided that death row inmates can no longer do penance by humbly accepting the punishment they deserve?

    I'm tired of Vatican II's emphasis on human dignity. Popes may need to remember two kinds of it. Even a sociopathic mass murderer keeps keeps the dignity God gives each of us by creating us in his image. But we increase or moral dignity by behaving virtuously or viciously.

    For 14.5 years, I was a pen pal to a prisoner who a lifer who became a Greek Orthodox monk in the Administrative Maximum in Florence, Colorado, the securest federal prison in the United States. He told me that the guards must watch inmates brawl because those employees aren't allowed to break up the fights. So, an inmate could murder someone when no prison official had the authority to prevent the killing during the battle.

    Here's something I wish I could have asked Pope John Paul II. In his encyclical "The Gospel of Life," he says the death penalty shouldn't be used when there are other ways to protect society from a criminal. But what must authorities do with a condemned man who ought to die for his crime? If there are nonlethal ways to protect people from him, why execute him. But if death is the only correct punishment, he may need to die right away.

    Bill McEnaney

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. What you said about guards not being allowed to break up fights at Supermax defies common sense and is not true.
      https://coloradosun.com/2021/12/07/usp-florence-jamarr-thompson-killed/

      Delete
    2. "I'm tired of Vatican II's emphasis on human dignity. Popes may need to remember two kinds of it. Even a sociopathic mass murderer keeps keeps the dignity God gives each of us by creating us in his image. But we increase or moral dignity by behaving virtuously or viciously."

      Actually, 'Dignitas Infinita' (7) deals with precisely this point:

      'The phrase “the dignity of the human person” risks lending itself to a variety of interpretations that can yield potential ambiguities and “contradictions that lead us to wonder whether the equal dignity of all human beings […] is truly recognized, respected, protected and promoted in every situation.” (Francis, 'Fratelli Tutti') This brings us to recognize the possibility of a fourfold distinction of the concept of dignity: ontological dignity, moral dignity, social dignity, and existential dignity. The most important among these is the ontological dignity that belongs to the person as such simply because he or she exists and is willed, created, and loved by God. Ontological dignity is indelible and remains valid beyond any circumstances in which the person may find themselves.

      'When we speak of moral dignity, we refer to how people exercise their freedom. While people are endowed with conscience, they can always act against it. However, were they to do so, they would behave in a way that is “not dignified” with respect to their nature as creatures who are loved by God and called to love others. Yet, this possibility always exists for human freedom, and history illustrates how individuals—when exercising their freedom against the law of love revealed by the Gospel—can commit inestimably profound acts of evil against others. Those who act this way seem to have lost any trace of humanity and dignity. This is where the present distinction can help us discern between the moral dignity that de facto can be “lost” and the ontological dignity that can never be annulled. And it is precisely because of this latter point that we must work with all our might so that all those who have done evil may repent and convert.'

      ('Dignitas Infinita' (8) then goes on to expound the other two meanings of 'dignity' - social and existential.)

      Delete
    3. Dignitas Infinita goes on to say Here, one should also mention the death penalty, for this also violates the inalienable dignity of every person, regardless of the circumstances. And it footnotes to the new 2267 Catechism for sourcing.

      It must be noted that although this document mentions the idea of moral dignity as something distinguishable from human dignity that stems from human nature itself, it then goes on to almost completely ignore it as a factor in the rest of the document. For example, it says It is also fitting to reaffirm the dignity of those who are incarcerated, who often must live in undignified conditions. It makes no explicit attempt to even call forth any clarification of what "conditions" violate their human rights, and what conditions properly reflect their moral status.

      Pope Francis, in more than one instance, gave comments indicating his rejection of life imprisonment for even the worst of murderers: he seemed to say that their "human dignity" required that society anticipate their return to civil life after a limited period of punishment. I would argue that his attitude effectively nullifies the very concept of punishment proportionate to the offense, and thus appears to conflict almost directly with JPII's statement that the state has the right and duty to impose proportionate punishments.

      And the document's reference to Vatican II's thesis “contemporary man is becoming increasingly conscious of the dignity of the human person; more and more people are demanding that men should exercise fully their own judgment and a responsible freedom in their actions and should not be subject to the pressure of coercion but be inspired by a sense of duty.”[28] Such freedom of thought and conscience, both individual and communal, is based on the recognition of human dignity “as known through the revealed Word of God and by reason itself” is clearly a mere sociological guesstimate of the state of affairs in the world. Just 1 decade after this statement, most of the western world legalized abortion. Within 3 more decades, euthanasia was being practiced regularly. The notion that modern men were being "increasingly conscious of the dignity of the human person" could ONLY be claimed by being equivocal on that "dignity", as they manifestly MISunderstood it in the majorities that voted for this for 50 years. This is not some minor quibble about "human dignity", it represents a basic framework error. So, the obvious mistake of Vatican II on this point undermines the VERY SAME claim by Pope Francis as a basis for changing p. 2267 in the Catechism, i.e. his sociological estimate of what people "recognize".

      Delete
  21. "the declaration Dignitas Infinita, issued by the DDF during Francis’s pontificate, implies that capital punishment is contrary even to natural law."
    One way to read the document vis-a-vis these points is to view it from the standpoint of Pope Francis's pragmatic rather than theological bent. When reading such qualifications as "regardless of circumstance," what he means is "regardless of circumstances *in the Christian present and future*." That's because it's not a claim about theory, but about future practice. There may well have been circumstances in (say) 4000 BC where it was permissible, but I think it would be difficult to say that Pope Francis intended to speak to that.
    The "human nature" bit is trickier, but there's probably a reading (however awkward).
    I guess I presently view these statements from Dignitas Infinita as similar to the way Feser views the statements from the Catechism -- not heterodox but not exactly a model of clarity either.

    ReplyDelete
  22. Some Catholics seem to be obsessed by this peripheral topic......

    ReplyDelete