Hylomorphism in brief
Longtime
readers of this blog or of my books will be familiar with the
Aristotelian-Thomistic conception of physical substances as composites of form
and matter, where (to a first approximation) matter is the stuff out of which such
a substance is made and form is what organizes that stuff in a way that allows
it to manifest its characteristic properties and powers. More precisely, it is substantial form that does so.
And the soul is a substantial form of the kind that gives a physical
substance the distinctive properties and powers of a living thing.
Matter, on
Aquinas’s account, is what makes it possible for there to be more than one instance
of any species of physical substance (using “species” here in the traditional
broad metaphysical sense, not the narrower biological sense). Different lumps of iron all have the same
basic nature, as do different oak trees and different poodles. But if they have the same nature, how can
they be different substances? The answer
is that there are different bits of matter which have all taken on the same
nature. Matter is in this way the “principle
of individuation” of physical substances.
When the
matter of a purely physical substance loses its substantial form, that
particular substance goes out of existence altogether. For example, when you chop down an oak tree
and burn it in the fireplace, that particular oak tree is gone. The matter out of which it is made persists,
but it has taken on an entirely different form, the form of ash. The substantial form of an oak tree is no
longer present in it (even though there are, of course, other oak trees, and they have such a substantial form).
Now, Aquinas
thinks of angels as substances that are purely intellectual in nature, and thus
(since he takes the intellect to be incorporeal) to be immaterial
substances. Because they are immaterial,
there is no way to individuate one member of an angelic species from
another. There can still be different
species of angel, but each will have exactly one member. Hence there are as many angelic species as
there are angels.
The human
intellect, like angelic intellects, is incorporeal. How, then, can there be more than one member
of the human species? The answer, for Aquinas,
is that while human beings are not purely corporeal substances (unlike iron,
oak trees, and poodles) neither are they purely
incorporeal substances (as angels are).
A human being is a unique sort of substance that has both corporeal
properties and powers (such as eating, walking, seeing, and hearing) and
incorporeal ones (thinking and willing).
Because
human beings are partly corporeal, they can be individuated from one another as
different members of the same species.
But because they are partly incorporeal, they do not go out of existence
altogether at death. They carry on as incomplete
substances after death, reduced to just their intellectual (and thus
incorporeal) operations. Because every
substance has a form, and human beings continue on as incomplete substances, a
human being’s form continues on after death.
And since the soul just is the substantial form of a human being, that means
that the soul carries on after death. It
no longer manifests the corporeal
powers that it would normally give human beings (since, absent the body, there’s
no matter for it to inform). But the incorporeal powers can still
manifest.
Vallicella’s objection
Bill begins
his criticism of this view by saying that Aristotelian-Thomistic hylomorphism holds
that “substances of the same kind have the same substantial form.” In the case of human beings, he continues, “since
these substances of the human kind have the same form, it is not their form
that makes them numerically different… It is the matter of their respective bodies that makes
numerically different human beings numerically different.”
But in that
case, Bill argues, when the matter of some particular human being goes at
death, there is nothing left to individuate him. Hence there can be nothing of him, in particular, that carries
on. Bill writes:
After death a human person ceases to exist as the particular
person that he or she is. But that is to
say that the particular person, Socrates say, ceases to exist, full stop. What survives is at best a form which is
common to all persons. That form,
however, cannot be you or me. Thus the
particularity, individuality, haecceity, ipseity of persons, which is essential
to persons, is lost at death and does not survive post mortem.
Bill appears
to think that if the Aristotelian-Thomistic view were applied consistently, it
would have to say of human beings what it says of iron, oak trees, and
poodles. Just as the particular
individual oak tree that you burn in the fireplace is altogether gone (even
though there are other oak trees that carry on), so too, after death, is the
particular individual human being altogether gone (even though there are other
human beings who carry on).
But there
are two problems with Bill’s argument.
The first is that it rests on a mistaken conception of substantial
form. The second is that it neglects the
crucial difference the Thomist says exists between human beings and every other
corporeal substance, which is that human beings have incorporeal intellectual
powers.
Let’s
consider these points in order. When
Bill says that, for hylomorphism, “substances of the same kind have the same
substantial form,” he speaks ambiguously.
That could mean that, while each individual physical substance has its
own substantial form, with physical substances of the same species their
substantial forms are of the same kind.
That would be a correct characterization of the Aristotelian-Thomistic
position, but unfortunately it does not seem to be what Bill means. He seems to mean instead that there is one
substantial form shared by all human beings in common – not one kind of substantial form, but one substantial form.
But that is
not what Aristotelian-Thomistic hylomorphism says, and it is not true. There are, it seems to me, two ways to read
Bill’s claim. On one reading, the
substantial form of human beings is a kind of Platonic Form, and different
human bodies are all human because they participate in that same one Form. The problem with this is that it isn’t an Aristotelian conception of form at all,
but a Platonic conception. A substantial
form, for the Aristotelian, isn’t an abstract Platonic object in which a thing
participates. Rather, it is a concrete
principle intrinsic to a substance that grounds its characteristic properties
and powers.
The other
way to read Bill’s characterization of hylomorphism is as holding that human
beings share one substantial form in the sense that they are all part of one
big substance – humanity considered as something like a single organism, with
different individual human beings as analogous to body parts that that organism
gains or loses as people are conceived or die.
But this is obviously not Aristotle’s or Aquinas’s view. They take human beings to be substances, not parts of a substance. And as
substances, each must have his own substantial form.
I think it’s
the first of these interpretations (what I’m characterizing as the Platonic
one), rather than the second, that Bill has in mind. But, again, it is a mistaken
interpretation. It just isn’t the case
that you, me, and Socrates all share the same one substantial form in the sense
Bill’s argument requires. Rather, you
have your own substantial form (and thus soul), I have mine, and Socrates has
his.
The same
thing is true of an oak tree. This oak
tree has its own individual substantial form, that oak tree has its own individual
substantial form, and so on. The reason
none of them continue after death is that everything an oak tree has or does –
and thus every property or power its substantial form gives it – depends on
matter. Hence when the matter goes,
there’s nothing left for the form to inform, nothing left for it to be the form
of.
This brings
us to the second crucial point, which is that a human being, unlike an oak
tree, has properties and powers that do not
depend on matter – namely, the intellectual properties and powers. Hence, a human being is not an entirely
corporeal substance, but a partly incorporeal one. This incorporeal part carries on after the
body dies, so that there is in this
case (unlike the case of the oak tree) something for the form to continue to be
the form of.
And that is
the sense in which the soul carries on beyond the death of the body. Yes, the soul is the form of the body,
because it is the form of a substance that it partially bodily in nature.
But unlike an oak or a poodle, a human being is not entirely bodily in nature, so that there is (as it were) still work
for the human soul to do even after the body is gone.
Why does
this not make the human soul after death like an angel, the unique member of
its own distinct species? The answer is
that the soul was once conjoined to its body and always retains its orientation
to that particular body. An angel
without a body is no less an angel for that.
It is complete in its incorporeal
mode of existence. By contrast, a human
being without a body (that is to say, a disembodied soul) is less of a human
being insofar as it is an incomplete
human being. Incorporeality is normal
for an angel, but not for a human being.
This orientation toward matter, which persists even in the absence of
matter, suffices to individuate human souls.
Of course, Bill
may raise further objections, to some or all of what I’ve said here. The point, though, is to indicate why I think
the particular objection he raises in his post fails. (Longtime readers might remember that this
issue is in fact a matter of longstanding dispute between Bill and me. I’ve linked to some earlier posts on the
subject below.)
I want to
add in closing that I have been reading Bill’s recent book Life’s Path with pleasure and profit, and advise you to do the
same. Bill is among the rare
contemporary philosophers who live up to the traditional ideal of producing both
solid technical academic philosophical work (as in his superb earlier book A Paradigm
Theory of Existence) and insightful moral, political, and other practical
reflections accessible to a more popular audience (as in the more recent
book). Read and learn.
Related
posts:
Vallicella
on hylemorphic dualism
I'm probably misunderstanding. But it seems to me that this passage....
ReplyDelete"The same thing is true of an oak tree. This oak tree has its own individual substantial form, that oak tree has its own individual substantial form, and so on. The reason none of them continue after death is that everything an oak tree has or does – and thus every property or power its substantial form gives it – depends on matter. Hence when the matter goes, there’s nothing left for the form to inform, nothing left for it to be the form of."
kind of obviates the need for matter as a principle of individuation. If each oak tree has its own (distinct) substantial form, then in fact, it did not need matter to individuate it. Each oak tree is its own species, like each angel.
No? What am I missing?