I appreciate their civility, and Fastiggi’s call at the end of the interview for charity in dealing with those who disagree. But their attempt fails. Much of what Fastiggi has to say are reheated claims that I have already refuted in past exchanges with him, such as the two-part essay I wrote in response to his series on the death penalty at Where Peter Is. (You can find it here and here. The essay was reprinted as a single long article in Ultramontanism and Tradition, edited by Peter Kwasniewski.) Fastiggi simply repeats his assertions without acknowledging, much less answering, my rebuttals. He also makes some new claims, which are no more plausible than the older ones. Let’s take a look.
A straw man
In any
fruitful discussion of this topic, it must constantly be kept in mind that there
are two questions that need to be clearly distinguished. First, is the death penalty intrinsically
wrong? And second, even if it is not
intrinsically wrong, is it nevertheless morally better never to resort to
it? To answer “Yes” to the first
question is to say that capital punishment of
its very nature, and regardless of the circumstances, is wrong, and thus
can never even in principle be used. But
someone could answer “No” to the first question and still answer “Yes” to the
second. To take this view is to say that
while in theory the death penalty could be justified in certain circumstances,
in practice those circumstances never obtain, at least not today, and that the
moral considerations that tell against its use outweigh those that speak in
favor of it.
People who
comment on the topic of Catholicism and capital punishment very frequently
ignore this distinction. The result is
that they often talk past one another and the discussion generates more heat
than light. Now, at the beginning of
their conversation, Fastiggi and Sonna are, to their credit, careful to note
the distinction. But unfortunately, later
in their discussion, they ignore it, and this leads them to attack a straw man.
In
particular, Fastiggi claims (after the 35 minute mark in the video) that “people
say, well, the Church has always taught, always allowed for the [death penalty].” Arguing against this, Fastiggi cites some
Fathers of the Church who were against capital punishment, and concludes that “it’s
almost like a myth, this 2,000 year old tradition, but if it’s repeated enough
by commentators and writers, then people begin to believe it.” Similarly, Sonna remarks (around the 45
minute mark) that “a lot of people have this impression that the Church, as if
it were this uniform block, this constant unchanging permanent wall, has just
consistently said the death penalty’s fine, you know, go ahead and do it.” But in fact, he continues, “historically,
there was an uneasiness at times with the death penalty.” Fastiggi and Sonna make a big deal out of this
theme, as if it is a damning point against Catholic defenders of the death
penalty.
But not so
fast. For here too we need to
distinguish two claims, namely:
(1) The
Church always taught for 2,000 years that the death penalty is not
intrinsically wrong.
(2) The
Church always taught for 2,000 years that the death penalty is not only not
intrinsically wrong, but that it is generally a good idea and should be used.
I know of
many Catholic defenders of capital punishment who have asserted claim (1),
including myself. But claim (1) is by no
means a “myth.” It is demonstrably true,
as Joseph Bessette and I document in detail in our book By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic
Defense of Capital Punishment.
Indeed, in his
own book on the subject, E. Christian Brugger, the foremost Catholic
theologian who argues against capital punishment – and someone who even claims
that the death penalty is
intrinsically wrong – admits that (1) is true.
In fact, even Fastiggi and Sonna appear to concede it. Fastiggi acknowledges that the Fathers he
cites “don’t necessarily challenge the state’s right to [execute],” but merely
argue against exercising that right. And
Sonna admits that “maybe we can’t dispute that the state has the right,
technically, to do it.”
By contrast,
claim (2) is indeed false, for just the reasons Fastiggi gives. But I cannot think of a single person who endorses
claim (2) in the first place. (Certainly
Joe Bessette and I explicitly acknowledge in our book that some Fathers and
popes held that it was morally better not to resort to the death penalty.) So, when Fastiggi cites what certain of the
Fathers say as evidence against a “myth” he alleges many are peddling, he is
attacking a thesis that no one in fact holds.
It seems otherwise to him and to Sonna only because they ignore the
distinction between (1) and (2).
Misrepresenting John Paul II
Sloppiness
of this kind often leads Fastiggi to misrepresent the views of his opponents
and the nature of their disagreement with him.
It also leads him to misrepresent a pope he appeals to in defense of his
position, namely Pope St. John Paul II. About
seven minutes into the video, Fastiggi suggests that the Church now condemns
not only killing the innocent, but “intentional killing” as such. He says:
The reason why the Church has now developed her teaching to
be opposed to capital punishment is because it involves intentional killing,
and then the question of course of whether or not a murderer loses human
dignity and the right to life. And
really, the turning point of this was St. John Paul II. In Evangelium
Vitae number 9, he says not even a murderer loses his dignity.
After the 50
minute mark, Fastiggi returns to the theme, and says:
I think a leap was made with the understanding that punishing
people by intentionally killing them is an offense against the inviolability of
life. The theoretical question is, does
a serious crime take away the right to life?
And John Paul II answered that in Evangelium
Vitae 9. That was the breakthrough,
that not even a murderer loses his dignity and right to life.
This is
sleight of hand. It is true that Evangelium
Vitae 9 says that “not even a murderer loses his personal
dignity.” But the encyclical nowhere
says that a murderer does not lose his right
to life. Instead, it speaks of “the
absolute inviolability of innocent
human life,” “the inviolable right to life of every innocent human being” and again, of “fundamental human rights,
beginning with the right to life of every innocent
human being”; it says that “as far as the right to life is concerned, every
innocent human being is absolutely
equal to all others”; it teaches that “a law which violates an innocent person's natural right to life
is unjust and, as such, is not valid as a law”; and it calls for “unconditional
respect for the right to life of every innocent
person” (emphasis added). And it
explicitly allows that the execution of those guilty of the gravest offenses is
permissible “in cases of absolute necessity.”
That would not be possible if the murderer never loses his right to
life.
It is true
that Evangelium Vitae also says that
bloodless means are preferable where possible because they are “more in line with human dignity” and “more in conformity to the dignity of the
human person.” But notice that that does
not entail that capital punishment is not
at all in line with human dignity, only that it is less in line with it.
(Compare: To say that Ricky is more talented than Fred does not entail
that Fred is altogether untalented; to say that Ethel is more intelligent than
Lucy does not entail that Lucy is altogether unintelligent; and so on.) So, from the claim that (a) not even a murderer loses his dignity, together
with the claim that (b) the death penalty
is less in line with human dignity than milder punishments, it simply does
not follow that (c) capital punishment is
flatly incompatible with the murderer’s dignity, and neither does it follow
that (d) the murderer does not lose his
right to life. Nor, again, does John
Paul II draw those conclusions.
Perhaps
Fastiggi would say that John Paul II should
have drawn those conclusions, and that in failing to do so he was being
inconsistent. But there are several
problems with such a response. First, it
wouldn’t change the fact that John Paul II did not in fact draw them, and thus did
not in fact say the things Fastiggi attributes to him. Second, for the reasons I have given, the
conclusions do not in fact follow logically from John Paul II’s premises, so
that the pope was not being inconsistent.
Third, if there are two ways of reading a papal document, in one of
which it contains an inconsistency and in the other of which it does not, the
second is to be preferred. Hence, for
that reason alone, we should reject Fastiggi’s reading. Fourth, Fastiggi’s reading would imply that
John Paul II was not only not consistent with himself, but also contradicted
his predecessors – such as Pope Pius XII, who taught:
Even when it is a question of the execution of a man
condemned to death, the State does not dispose of the individual's right to
live. It is reserved rather to the
public authority to deprive the criminal of the benefit of life when already,
by his crime, he has deprived himself of
the right to live. (Address to the First International Congress on the
Histopathology of the Nervous System, 1952, emphasis added)
Certainly,
implicitly to accuse one pope (John Paul II) of inconsistency and another pope (Pius
XII) of grave moral error is a strange way to try to defend a third pope
(Francis)!
In any
event, Joe Bessette and I provide a very detailed analysis of John Paul II’s
teaching at pp. 144-82 of our book. As
we demonstrate there, when one considers the entirety of the evidence (and not
just the usual cherry-picked phrases Catholic opponents of capital punishment
like to quote), it is crystal clear that the pope’s teaching was in no way an
alteration or even development of traditional doctrine, but simply a prudential
judgment about how to apply that doctrine to contemporary circumstances. Like so many of our critics, Fastiggi offers
no response at all to the arguments we give there, but pretends they don’t
exist.
Obfuscating on Pope Francis
Beginning at
about 12 minutes into their discussion, Fastiggi and Sonna argue that Pope
Francis has, in any event, not actually taught that the death penalty is
intrinsically wrong. They focus on the
pope’s 2018 revision to the Catechism, and suggest that it implicitly
acknowledges that capital punishment is permissible in theory, and simply
teaches that it is inadmissible under current circumstances.
This is a
defensible position, as far as it goes.
I have always myself acknowledged that the revision can and should be
read in such a way that it is not teaching that capital punishment is
intrinsically evil. But that is only
part of the story. For one thing, the
problem with the revision is that this is not a natural reading of it. The
revised text characterizes the death penalty as “an attack on the inviolability
and dignity of the person.” On a natural
reading, that seems to imply that capital punishment is intrinsically at odds with human dignity (rather than being at odds
with it only if certain conditions
fail to hold), and thus intrinsically
wrong. Yes, it need not be read that
way, but magisterial statements should be clearly
consistent with traditional teaching, not merely consistent with it on a
strained reading.
For another
thing, other magisterial statements made during Pope Francis’s pontificate are
much harder to reconcile with the traditional teaching. For example, in a
2017 address, the pope asserted that “the death penalty is an
inhumane measure that, regardless of how
it is carried out, abases human dignity.
It is per se contrary to the
Gospel” (emphasis added). The
italicized phrases are most naturally read as claiming that capital punishment
is always and intrinsically wrong.
Some might
reply that this entails only that the death penalty is contrary to the higher
demands of Christian morality, not that it is contrary to natural law. That would be bad enough, because (as I have
shown elsewhere, such as in this
article) the traditional teaching of the Church is that it is not contrary to Christian morality any
more than it is contrary to natural law.
But to make
matters worse, the declaration Dignitas
Infinita, issued by the DDF during Francis’s pontificate,
implies that capital punishment is
contrary even to natural law. For it
asserts that “the death penalty… violates the inalienable dignity of every
person, regardless of the circumstances,” and that this dignity is grounded in
“human nature apart from all cultural change.” The declaration also asserts that human
dignity must be upheld “beyond every circumstance,” “in all circumstances,”
“regardless of the circumstances,” and so on. Here there is no wiggle room for saying that
the document judges capital punishment to be contrary to human dignity only if
certain conditions are not met. For it
flatly asserts that it violates human dignity “regardless of the
circumstances.” Nor is there any wiggle
room for saying that the document nevertheless allows in principle for such a
violation of human dignity under certain circumstances (which would be a
bizarre idea in any case). For it
explicitly says that human dignity “prevails in and beyond every circumstance,
state, or situation the person may ever encounter,” and so on. The logical implication of all this is that
capital punishment is absolutely ruled out as always and intrinsically wrong. And that straightforwardly contradicts
traditional teaching.
Sonna, at
least, appears to acknowledge that the traditional teaching cannot be
reversed. So, if he is going to be
consistent, he will have to admit that these statements issued during Francis’s
pontificate are problematic – that they are poorly formulated at best, and
erroneous at worst (which is possible in non-ex cathedra magisterial statements).
Parallel doctrinal reversals?
Fastiggi is
another story. At around 40 minutes in,
he says: “But hasn’t the Church definitively taught that the death penalty is
allowed? No, it hasn’t.” And earlier, at around 25 minutes in, he says
that “even if the Church has not yet, maybe someday she’ll say it’s
intrinsically immoral, but because it had been accepted for so long we don’t
need to say that right now.”
But Fastiggi
is simply mistaken. When all the
relevant evidence is taken account of, it is manifest that the doctrine that
the death penalty is not intrinsically wrong has been taught by both scripture
and the Church in an irreformable manner.
I set out some of this evidence in a
long Catholic World Report article
from some years back, and Joe Bessette and I do so in greater depth in our
book. Fastiggi says nothing even to
acknowledge, much less answer, these arguments.
He merely begs the question against them.
Fastiggi
also says that even if the Church does not hold that the death penalty is
intrinsically wrong, it doesn’t follow that its teaching against it is merely a
prudential judgment which Catholics need only respectfully consider but not
necessarily follow. For the Church has
the authority to prohibit even certain practices that are not inherently
wrong. Fastiggi gives the example of
cremation, which was for a long time prohibited by the Church but now is
permitted under certain circumstances. He
also cites polygamy and divorce, which were tolerated under the old covenant
but have been forbidden under the new covenant.
Fastiggi is
right about that much, but these facts don’t suffice to show that the Church
can do more than issue a non-binding prudential judgment against use of the
death penalty. The reason is that it is
the state and not the Church which has the responsibility and right under
natural law to do what is necessary to ensure the safety of the community. This is why, after setting out the criteria
for fighting a just war, the Catechism goes on to say that “the evaluation of
these conditions for moral legitimacy belongs to the prudential judgment of
those who have responsibility for the common good” (2309). In other words, the Church can teach that a
war is just only when the cause is just, there is a serious chance of success, no
other options are likely to work, and so on.
But the Church does not have the expertise or authority to determine how
these criteria apply in a particular case.
For example, it does not have the relevant expertise to determine
whether some option other than war would suffice to repel an aggressor in a
particular case, or whether a certain military strategy is likely to
succeed. These are matters of prudential
judgment, and it is the state rather than the Church that has the right and
responsibility to make that judgment.
But the same
applies, mutatis mutandis, to capital
punishment. The revision to the
catechism claims, for example, that modern systems of imprisonment are
sufficient to protect others against the most dangerous offenders. But the Church has no more expertise on that
sort of issue than it does on military strategy. If government officials have good empirical
reason to believe that the death penalty saves lives – for example, if they
have evidence that it has a significant deterrent effect, or that it is needed
to protect prison guards or other prisoners from the most violent offenders –
then they have just as much a right under natural law to utilize capital
punishment as they do to fight a just war.
This sort of
reasoning does not apply to cremation, which is why it is not an interesting
parallel to the case of capital punishment.
The examples of polygamy and divorce also do nothing to help Fastiggi’s
case, and not just because (unlike capital punishment) the state does not need
to keep them open as options in order to do its job of protecting society. There is also the following glaring
disanalogy: The New Testament explicitly forbids
divorce and clearly opposes polygamy too, as has the Church ever since. But the New Testament explicitly allows capital punishment (e.g. in
Romans 13), as has the Church ever since.
Cremation, polygamy, and divorce thus offer no precedent for an absolute
prohibition on capital punishment.
Fastiggi and
Sonna suggest other alleged doctrinal reversals that they think provide a
precedent for a reversal on capital punishment.
But they are all bad analogies that provide no support whatsoever for
such a reversal. For example, Fastiggi
points to the fact that theologians were once free to disagree about the
Immaculate Conception, but later the Church made a dogmatic pronouncement on
the matter so that such legitimate disagreement is no longer possible.
The problem
with this purported analogy should be obvious.
To teach that capital punishment is intrinsically wrong would directly
contradict what the Church had consistently taught for 2,000 years and what she
had always understood scripture to teach.
Proclaiming the dogma of the Immaculate Conception involved nothing
remotely like that. In particular, it in
no way involved the Church contradicting
some doctrine she had previously taught.
Fastiggi
alleges that there is also a parallel between capital punishment and the case
of torture. He contrasts a passing
remark on the subject from Pope Innocent I, which left its use open, with the
more recent teaching of the Church condemning torture. Here too the alleged parallel is
spurious. The Church holds that
scripture cannot teach moral error, and she has for two millennia acknowledged
that scripture repeatedly sanctions capital punishment. But there is no such scriptural sanction for
torture. The Church has also for two
millennia herself consistently and clearly taught that capital punishment can
under certain circumstances be licit, to the point of including this doctrine
in major teaching documents such as the catechisms of Pope St. Pius V and Pope
St. John Paul II. The teaching was also
endorsed by the Fathers (even those who opposed the use of capital punishment
in practice), has been consistently affirmed by the Church’s greatest
theologians (including many Doctors of the Church), and routinely endorsed in
approved manuals of moral theology. None
of this can be said of torture.
Fastiggi and
Sonna also suggest that the development of the Church’s teaching on slavery
provides a precedent for a change on capital punishment. But this alleged parallel too is phony. For one thing, here too Fastiggi and Sonna
muddy the waters by ignoring long-established and crucial distinctions. For the word “slavery” is ambiguous. What most people think of when they hear this
term is chattel slavery, which
involves claiming ownership of another human being in the way one might own an
animal or inanimate object. The Church
does indeed teach that this is intrinsically evil, but she has never taught
otherwise. Indeed, she has condemned
this practice for centuries (as I document in my book All One in
Christ: A Catholic Critique of Racism and Critical Race Theory).
There are,
however, less extreme forms of servitude that the Church has taken to be at
least in theory not unjust. In
particular, there is penal servitude,
which is forced labor in punishment for a crime. The idea here is that if the state can, in
punishment for a sufficiently grave crime, take away an offender’s liberty for
a prolonged period of time (even for life), then it can also require him to
work. And there is indentured servitude, a prolonged period of labor without payment
as a way to repay a debt or in exchange for some benefit. The idea here is that if someone can
legitimately enter a work contract, or have his wages garnished in order to pay
a debt, then by extension he can make himself a servant in order to pay a debt.
The trouble
with these practices is that in concrete circumstances they are fraught with
moral hazard, and were often used to rationalize what amounted to chattel
slavery (such as when captives taken in war were enslaved on the spurious
grounds that they were guilty of the offense of fighting an unjust war, and
thus could be forced into penal servitude).
Hence, moral theologians settled on the view (quite correctly, I would
say) that when all relevant moral considerations are brought to bear, it is
clear that they ought flatly to be banned altogether.
There is
also the consideration that in scripture, slavery is merely tolerated as an
institution that happened to exist, rather than put forward as a positive
good. By contrast, the death penalty is not merely tolerated, but in some cases
is positively sanctioned (not only in the Mosaic law, but in other contexts
such as Genesis 9 and Romans 13).
So, when all
the distinctions are made, the argument that “the Church reversed herself on
slavery, so she can reverse herself on capital punishment” falls apart. There was no such reversal, and thus no
precedent for a reversal on capital punishment.
Magisterial credibility
This brings
us to Fastiggi’s remarks about Genesis 9 and Romans 13, where he repeats claims
that I have already refuted in my previous exchange with him. And once again, he simply ignores rather than
answers the objections I raised there. I
direct the interested reader to that
earlier essay of mine. (In
particular, see the sections titled “Genesis and the death penalty” and “The
Mosaic Law versus the Gospel?”)
Fastiggi
acknowledges that, in the instruction Donum
Veritatis, the Church affirms that Catholics have the right
respectfully to raise questions about deficient magisterial statements and ask
for clarification. He says that this
nevertheless gives Catholics no right to “dissent” from the teaching of the
Church. I agree with him about all
that. But Fastiggi seems to think that
it rules out the sort of respectful criticisms that I and others with the
relevant expertise have raised. It does
not, and I have many times given arguments that show that it does not. These arguments too are ones that Fastiggi
simply ignores rather than tries to answer.
For example,
the criticisms I have raised with respect to the 2018 revision of the Catechism
have nothing to do with “dissenting” from some teaching of the Church. Rather, the whole point is that the teaching
is unclear – that it is far from obvious exactly
what it is that Catholics are being asked to assent to. True, the revision
declares that the death penalty is now “inadmissible.” But the trouble is that the force of this teaching is not
obvious. I
have argued that there are only two ways to read it. On the one hand, it might be read as claiming
that the death penalty is intrinsically
wrong and thus “inadmissible” in an absolute
and unqualified way. The problem is
that this would contradict scripture and tradition, and thus amount to a
doctrinal error (something that can occur in non-ex cathedra statements). Moreover, even Fastiggi and Sonna
acknowledge that this is not the right way to read it.
But when we
take account of all the relevant considerations (both from within the document
and from the larger tradition of the Church), the only other way to read it is
as saying that the death penalty is “inadmissible” unless certain conditions hold (such as that resort to it is necessary
in order to protect society). And if
this is the case, then the teaching amounts to a non-binding prudential
judgment. For the “unless” part is not
something concerning which the Church has any special authority. For example, whether capital punishment has a
significant deterrence effect, and whether modern prison systems really do
afford the means of protecting others from all violent offenders, are empirical
matters of social science, not matters of faith or morals.
For seven
years now, Fastiggi and I have been arguing about this issue, and in all that
time I have never gotten a clear answer from him about what a third possible
interpretation would look like. In any
event, if someone asks me “Do you dissent from the teaching of the revision of
the Catechism?” my answer is “No, I do not dissent from it. I assent to it, and interpret it in the only
way I know of that makes sense – namely, as a non-binding prudential
judgment.” I also say, however, that the
revision is badly formulated and potentially misleading. And I have every right respectfully to raise
such a criticism, by the norms set out in Donum
Veritatis. Fastiggi and others may
continue to yell “Dissent!” but yelling is all they would be doing. I have yet to hear an actual argument showing that my position
amounts to dissent.
I
acknowledge that my criticism of Dignitas
Infinita goes beyond this. Here, I
think we have a document that is not merely ambiguous, but very hard (at best)
to defend from the charge of flatly contradicting scripture and tradition and
thus being erroneous. But if someone has
a plausible way of reconciling it with scripture and tradition, I’m all
ears.
Even if it
is indeed in error, however, this is possible in non-ex cathedra documents.
Indeed, Fastiggi himself is implicitly committed to this thesis. For, again, he holds that the Church could
end up teaching that capital punishment is intrinsically immoral. And if that were correct, it would follow
that for two millennia, the Church got things gravely wrong on matters of basic
moral principle and biblical interpretation.
That is a very radical claim, and indeed far more radical than anything I have said. If I am right, then one pope has gotten
things wrong about capital punishment.
If Fastiggi is right, then every previous
pope who has taught on this topic has been wrong, as have the Fathers and
Doctors of the Church (and indeed scripture itself). Fastiggi likes to paint views like mine as
extreme, but in fact it is his views
that are extreme.
The fact
that he presents them politely and under the guise of obedience to the
magisterium doesn’t change that one whit.
It is the content of the views
that matter, and the content is radically subversive of the credibility of the
Church, because it implies that the Church
may have been gravely in error about a matter of natural law, the demands of
the Gospel, and the proper understanding of scripture for her entire history
until now. And if she could be that
wrong for that long, what else might she be wrong about?
At about one
hour and three minutes into the interview, Fastiggi says, with no sense of
irony: “There has to be trust in the Holy Spirit’s guidance of the
magisterium. And that’s what I find
missing in many of these papal critics.
They don’t trust the Holy Spirit.”
Yet Fastiggi is the one
suggesting that the magisterium may have, for two millennia, consistently erred
about a grave matter of natural law, Christian morality, and scriptural interpretation. Fastiggi
is the one suggesting that the Holy Spirit might have permitted this. But what is more likely – that that is the
case, or that a single pope (Francis) issued a badly formulated catechism
revision and permitted the DDF to slip a doctrinal error into a declaration? I submit that, if the Holy Spirit truly is
guiding the magisterium, the scenario I posit is manifestly more plausible than
the one Fastiggi is positing.
The reality
is that the critics do trust in the Holy
Spirit’s guidance of the magisterium.
They trust that the Holy Spirit would not have allowed the Church to be
that wrong for that long about something that important, so that it must be
those who now contradict the past magisterium who are mistaken. This has always been theoretically possible,
because the Church has always acknowledged that non-definitive exercises of the
magisterium can fall into error. Indeed
this has in fact happened before in the case even of papal teaching, as the famous
examples of popes Honorius I and John XXII illustrate. And Fastiggi’s own position entails it. If, as he insists, it may turn out that two
millennia of past teaching of the magisterium on capital punishment was wrong,
then it follows logically that it is also possible that it is instead Pope
Francis’s statements on the subject that are wrong. And as I have shown elsewhere (here
and here),
the Church has also always affirmed that there can be cases where the faithful
may respectfully criticize the magisterium, even a pope, for teaching contrary
to the tradition.
What Fastiggi
never seems to appreciate is that his approach damages the credibility of the
magisterium by appearing to saddle it with what, in logic, is known as a “No
True Scotsman” fallacy. Suppose I say
“No true Scotsman would be an empiricist,” and you respond “But David Hume was
an empiricist!” And suppose I reply “Well,
then David Hume must not really have
been a true Scotsman,” and that I insist that everybody has for 250 years been
misinterpreting all the evidence that seems obviously to show that he was an
empiricist. Needless to say, this would
not lend me or my thesis any credibility at all, but would do precisely the
opposite. It would reveal me to be
intellectually dishonest and unwilling to look at the evidence objectively.
Now, the
First Vatican Council declared that “the Holy Spirit was promised to the
successors of Peter not so that they might, by his revelation, make known some
new doctrine.” The Second Vatican
Council stated that “the living teaching office of the Church… is not above the
word of God, but serves it, teaching only what has been handed on.” Pope Benedict XVI taught that the pope “must
not proclaim his own ideas… he is bound to the great community of faith of all
times, to the binding interpretations that have developed throughout the
Church's pilgrimage.”
But the
liceity in principle of the death penalty has for two millennia been
consistently taught by the Church, and has for two millennia been understood by
the Church to be the teaching of scripture, which is the word of God. Hence, for a pope to teach that the death
penalty is intrinsically immoral would manifestly be a case of attempting to
“make known some new doctrine.” It would
manifestly be a case of putting himself “above the word of God” instead of
“teaching only what has been handed on.”
It would manifestly be a case of attempting to “proclaim his own ideas”
rather than being “bound to the great community of faith of all times.”
Fastiggi,
however, takes the view that if a pope were to teach such a thing, then the conclusion
we should draw is that the liceity in principle of capital punishment must
after all not really ever have been
the teaching of scripture; that it must not really
be a “new doctrine” but somehow implicit in what scripture and the Church have
always taught; that it must not really
after all have been among “the binding interpretations” to which a pope must
conform himself. And that is like
dogmatically insisting that Hume must not really
have been a true Scotsman after all. It
gives aid and comfort to Protestant and skeptical critics of Catholicism, who
argue that the Church’s claim to continuity with scripture and tradition is a
sham – that at the end of the day, the popes will just teach whatever they like
and then arbitrarily slap the label “traditional” on it.
It may be
that Fastiggi is not sufficiently sensitive to this problem, whereas I have
always emphasized it, in part because of the differences in our academic and
intellectual contexts. Fastiggi is a
theologian teaching at a seminary, the primary job of which is the formation of
priests. And it seems that he writes
pretty much exclusively for Catholic audiences.
I’m a philosopher teaching at a secular college, who often writes on
matters of apologetics. And my writing
is directed as much to the general public as it is to fellow Catholics. When Fastiggi sees Catholics criticizing even
obviously deficient magisterial statements, even in a respectful and well-informed
way, his instinctive reaction appears to be: “It’s unseemly for Catholics to be
doing that, no matter what the pope says!
Just keep quiet, and trust providence to sort it out.” When I see Catholics tying themselves in
logical knots trying to defend obviously deficient magisterial statements, my
instinctive reaction is: “Those are manifestly terrible arguments, you’re
making Catholicism look ridiculous! Just
frankly admit that there’s a problem, and trust providence to sort it out.” What Fastiggi and I agree about is that
providence will sort it out, but we disagree about what form this might take
and what role respectful criticism of deficient magisterial statements can play.
At the end of the day, though, such psychological speculations are not what matter. What matters is what the evidence of scripture, tradition, and the entirety of the magisterial history of the Church (not just the last few years of it) have to say. And as I have argued, that evidence tells decisively against Fastiggi’s position.
No comments:
Post a Comment