I won’t
repeat here everything I said in the earlier article, but the relevant
principles are as follows. Natural
rights, in general, exist for the purpose of facilitating the realization of
the ends toward which our nature directs us.
In the case of our rational and communicative powers, that end is the
discovery and dissemination of what is true and good. We have a natural right to speech that
facilitates this end. And while that
entails that there is no right to express erroneous or bad ideas as such, it nevertheless does allow for
a wide range of freedom to express even ideas that happen to be erroneous or bad.
The reason is that, given the limitations on our cognitive powers, we
are bound to fall into error sometimes, and the normal means of correcting
these errors is the give and take of discussion and debate. Furthermore, those who would censor erroneous
and bad ideas are (since they are no less human than anyone else) themselves prone to error, and therefore
may end up censoring true and good ideas.
There is a
presumption, then, in favor of free expression, precisely because it
facilitates the natural end of our rational powers. However, not all forms of expression are
protected by this presumption, because not all forms of expression have
anything to do with our rational powers.
For example, pornography does not appeal to our rationality and in no
way contributes to discovering truth or to debate by which we might root out
error. It appeals instead to our
appetites, and in a way that corrupts them.
In particular, it fosters and even habituates sexual desire that is
disordered in its intensity and its objects.
It thereby corrupts sexual morals, and thereby weakens the institution
of the family, the foundation of all social order. Accordingly, pornography is in no way
protected by the natural right to free speech.
There are
also ideas which not only happen to be erroneous or bad, but have a tendency positively to frustrate the pursuit of
truth and the living of good lives.
Examples would be views that deny the very reality of truth or goodness
as objective features of the world.
Since the purpose of the right to free expression is to safeguard the
pursuit and dissemination of what is true and good, it can hardly protect
speech that denies the very reality of the true and the good. Hence there can be no natural right to
promote such ideas. There may under
certain circumstances be good prudential reasons to tolerate them, but not because suppressing them would be inherently
unjust.
The case for (certain kinds of)
censorship
Which forms
of expression should the state prohibit, then?
To start with the least controversial examples, it should prohibit libelous
and slanderous speech, and speech that directly incites violence against some
individual or group.
That
pornography should be outlawed is now a more controversial claim than it used
to be, but it should not be controversial.
From a natural law point of view, this is not a difficult case at
all. Pornography should simply be
banned. To be sure, there are materials
concerning which one can make a case for toleration (for example, novels or
mainstream movies that are not pornographic works but do have salacious
content). But this is not so where straightforwardly
pornographic materials are concerned.
(Naturally, the argument for this claim presupposes the general natural
law account of sexual morality. I’m
aware that not every reader will accept that account, but my point is that if
one accepts it, together with the natural law account of the foundations of
natural rights, the case for outlawing pornography is obvious. I’ve defended the natural law approach to
sexual morality in
other writings.)
In a
forthcoming article at Postliberal Order,
I argue that governments have a right under natural law to prohibit flag
burning, understood as a public expression of contempt for one’s country. On the one hand, such a prohibition in no way
frustrates expression of or debate about any idea (since any idea that could be
expressed by burning the flag could be expressed instead in words). And on the other hand, showing such public
contempt for one’s country offends against the virtue of piety, and can
destabilize the social order by encouraging others to have a similar
contempt. But whether a particular
government should actually exercise
its natural right to ban this particular form of expression is a matter for
prudential judgment and depends on circumstances.
What about
the expression of ideas that positively frustrate the pursuit of what is true
or good? Here the clearest cases concern
contexts where such ideas might influence the young – who, because they are
more ignorant and inexperienced, and governed more by feeling than reason, are
least likely to be able to see what is wrong with such ideas. Hence, consider cognitive or moral relativist
theories that deny the reality of truth or goodness as objective features of
the world. Or consider theories that are
inherently subversive of the social order and pit one group against another,
such as Nazism, Marxism, and Critical Race Theory. Or theories which promote gravely disordered
sexual desires, and thus inculcate sexual vice in the young and destabilize the
family. It is simply common sense that
there cannot be a right to teach such ideas to young people, such as high
schoolers (let alone even younger children).
The state may and ought to prohibit the dissemination of such ideas in
primary and secondary education.
Things are
more complicated where higher education is concerned. Certainly the state should in no way and
under no circumstances actively promote
such evil ideas in any context, including higher education. But what about merely tolerating them? Here there
is no “one size fits all” answer, and much depends on the judgment of
prudence. There can be special
circumstances where the state has an interest in rooting out such ideas. For example, you would not want to tolerate
having many Critical Race Theorists on the faculties of the military academies,
because their ideas are positively subversive of allegiance to the country that
warriors are supposed to be protecting.
The case against (other kinds of)
censorship
But policing
academia in general is much trickier. Government
regulators are highly unlikely to be sufficiently good judges of ideas, given
the people who would be appointing them.
Liberal politicians tend to be suckers for every idiotic academic fad
that comes down the pike, while conservative politicians tend to be philistines.
Any regulation of academic discussion
coming from either left-wing flakes or right-wing yahoos would be ham-handed at
best and do much more harm than good.
Hence in a university context it is, in general, best to combat
erroneous ideas through the give and take of free debate.
Something
similar can be said of public debate in the world beyond academia, especially
in a pluralistic society like the U.S. whose constitution and political culture
have long idealized the free exchange of ideas (even if, in practice, not
always doing so consistently or well). When
it comes to bad ideas concerning political philosophy, public policy, and the
like (as opposed to defamatory speech, incitement to violence, pornographic expression,
and the like), it is better to fight them through the give and take of debate
rather than through censorship.
The COVID-19
pandemic vividly illustrated how dangerous it can be for even intelligent and
well-informed people with good intentions to try to police such speech. One side tried, in the name of public health,
to shout down critical discussion of policies that imposed severe costs on
millions yet whose scientific and moral justifiability was far from
certain. The other side, rightly alarmed
at this, overreacted by too willingly embracing crackpot medical ideas and
conspiracy theories. The first side then
condemned this overreaction, arrogantly oblivious to its own responsibility for
causing it.
In this
case, preemptively shutting down debate was especially unreasonable given how
poorly understood the virus was at first, and how draconian and untested were
the methods employed for dealing with it.
But even in the case of matters that are very well understood, it is
generally a bad idea to try to suppress dissent by force of law. Human beings are, by nature, rational animals. True, they very commonly use their rational
powers badly, and are prone to all sorts of error and irrational thinking. But because they are rational animals, they are,
naturally, prone to accept ideas only when they can see why they are reasonable
and have a choice about whether to embrace them. They do not react well to having forced on them ideas they don’t
understand or agree with, even when those ideas happen to be correct and resistance
to them is unreasonable. For the sake of
social harmony, then, there is a strong presumption against censoring public discussion
and debate over matters of policy, political philosophy, and the like.
In theory,
there are cases where this presumption can be overridden. But I would suggest that a necessary condition
for such censorship is that it meets all of the following criteria:
1. It should concern expression that is
inherently contrary to the common good, and in particular that attacks the
prerequisites of living together as a community of rational animals.
Again, I
would argue that examples of expression that meet this condition include: libelous
or slanderous speech; the incitement of violence against particular individuals
or groups; pornographic expression; direct assaults on the virtue of piety,
such as public actions intended to foster contempt for one’s country; ideas
that challenge the very reality of truth or goodness; and ideologies that
promote social conflict by demonizing entire groups of human beings, or which directly
promote grave vices such as sexual immorality.
(This list is meant to be illustrative, not exhaustive.) As I have said, there may be pragmatic
reasons why a government should tolerate such errors, but it cannot be wrong in
principle to suppress them.
Now, the
point is that these sorts of expression are direct
assaults on the good of individuals and societies. Defamatory speech, by destroying one’s
reputation, can make it extremely difficult or impossible to engage in everyday
social life (by securing employment, for example). This is even more obviously true of speech
that causes others to live under the threat of violence. A culture that is so awash in pornography
that even children have easy access to it will inevitably inculcate widespread
and deeply ingrained sexual vice, which is contrary to both our social nature
(since it destabilizes the family) and our rational nature (given that, as
Aquinas teaches, sexual vice has an even greater tendency than other vices do
to blind the intellect). The
proliferation of ideas that promote hatred of one’s country or of large groups
of one’s fellow citizens radically undermines social harmony. And so on.
Contrast
these examples with the following: disagreements over particular policy
proposals (concerning taxation, immigration, health care policy, foreign
policy, or the like); disagreement with or dislike of some particular
individual politician or political party; disagreements about particular moral
issues or matters of political philosophy (of the kind that always inevitably
arise in political debate, journals of opinion, the classroom, etc.); disagreements
about particular matters of empirical fact, concerning current events, history,
science, etc.; and so on.
These sorts
of disagreements, even when heated, are a normal part of social and political
life and in no way intrinsically at
odds with the good of individuals or societies.
And even when erroneous opinions about such matters result from outright
deception or intellectual dishonesty, they rarely strike at the very roots of
the social order. Moreover, it is in any
case simply unrealistic to suppose that government can, in general, effectively
separate such lies out from the honest mistakes and exaggerations human beings
are commonly prone to. Hence these are
matters where government should not
interfere with speech, but rather let error be corrected via the give and take
of free debate.
2. It should clearly be motivated by service to the common good, rather than the narrow interests of some particular party or leader.
The point
here is that it is not good enough for a policy of censorship actually to have
sound reasons in its favor. It must be motivated by those reasons, and be
widely perceived as having such a motivation.
Even the best policy is likely to backfire if it is widely perceived to
be motivated instead by corruption or a personal grudge on the part of some
leader, or by an attempt by one party or ideology to silence reasonable dissent.
This does
not mean that every single citizen has to think the policy has a good
motivation. That would, of course, be an
unrealistically stringent standard. But
a critical mass of the population has to be able to see it that way. Think of the way that, in wartime, the bulk
of the population often gives the government the benefit of the doubt where
certain censorship is concerned, because it knows that certain matters have to
be kept secret for the sake of national security. Certainly this was true in the days of World
War II, for example.
Of course, things
are different now, and distrust of governmental authority is much higher. But that makes it even more important (not less) for a critical mass of the population to
be able to believe that a censorship policy is at least intended to serve the common good rather than some narrow personal
or partisan interest. From the point of
view of natural law, the whole point of suppressing certain kinds of expression
is to preserve the social order and the common good. Hence a policy that will, in practice, tend
only further to divide an already highly polarized society can hardly be
justified on natural law grounds.
For these
reasons, even when a policy of censorship has good arguments in its favor, it
should in general not be pursued except by leaders known for the utmost probity
and statesmanship. Otherwise it is
likely to do more harm than good.
3. It should be calmly and carefully
thought out, not impulsive.
Censorship,
like war, is so grave in its consequences that even when it is justifiable, it
should never be resorted to lightly. Hence,
a policy of censorship should never be implemented except after careful and dispassionate
study. Major events that trigger strong
emotions (such as the rapid spread of COVID-19 in early 2020 and the recent
assassination of Charlie Kirk) often lead to calls for censorship. But censorship policies proposed under such
circumstances are the least likely to
be justifiable, because they result more from emotion than reason.
4. It should as far as possible be
implemented in general rules, rather than in ad hoc directives or other
exercises of discretionary power.
This condition
is a corollary of the second and third conditions. Where some individual or agency has arbitrary
power to censor speech, it is far more likely that such censorship will result
from the passions of the moment than careful and dispassionate analysis, and
that it will reflect personal or partisan interests rather than be directed to
the common good. There is also the
consideration that social order requires predictability, and thus the rule of
law rather than governance by whim.
In light of
these criteria, what should we think of recent Trump administration policies
that have been characterized as exercises in censorship? The answer is that it depends on which
policies we are talking about. In the
case of eliminating federal funding for DEI programs, rooting “woke” ideologies
out of the military academies, and the like, I would say that these measures
are all justifiable. One might quibble
over details of implementation, but the basic policies are sound, because these
ideas are poisonous and divisive and should have no influence on, or support
from, government.
But things
are very different with some of what has been said and done over the last
couple of weeks, in the aftermath of Charlie Kirk’s assassination. Attorney General Pam Bondi has spoken of
“going after” those who engage in vaguely defined “hate speech,” and of prosecuting
printing businesses that refuse to print Charlie Kirk posters. While ABC was in my view correct
to suspend Jimmy Kimmel for an unjust and inflammatory remark, it did so in part
under threat from FCC chairman Brendan Carr, whose action has
been compared by Republican Senator Ted Cruz to that of a mafia boss. President Trump has suggested that because
the negative press coverage he has received is in his view excessive, it is “no
longer free speech” and “illegal.”
These
remarks and actions are foolish and irresponsible. They are bad in themselves, because they
clearly do not meet the criteria set out in 1- 4 above. They also threaten to discredit the good
things the Trump administration is doing, because they give its enemies
ammunition by lending plausibility in the public mind to the tiresome charge of
“fascism.”
Defenders of the administration will point out that left-wingers who promoted “cancel culture,” cheered Trump’s being kicked off of social media, suppressed speech during the pandemic, etc. have little standing to complain. That is correct. But it is also irrelevant. It’s a cliché to say that two wrongs don’t make a right, but it is also true. Statesmanship requires doing whatever possible to repair social divisions, not exacerbating them further in the interests of getting revenge on those who first caused them.
No comments:
Post a Comment