Stop me if
you’ve heard this one before, but while
we’re on the subject of humor, here’s another mistake that is often made in
discussions of it: failing to identify precisely which aspect of the phenomenon of humor a theory is (or is best
interpreted as) trying to explain. For
instance, this is sometimes manifest in lists of the various “theories of
humor” put forward by philosophers over the centuries.
Friday, August 28, 2015
Tuesday, August 25, 2015
Dragging the net
My recent Claremont Review of Books review of
Scruton’s Soul of the World and
Wilson’s The Meaning of Human Existence
is
now available for free online.
Should we
expect a sound proof to convince everyone?
Michael Augros investigates
at Strange Notions (in an excerpt
from his new book Who
Designed the Designer? A Rediscovered Path to God's Existence).
Intrigue! Conspiracy!
Comic books! First, where did the
idea for Spider-Man really come from? The
New York Post reports on a Brooklyn
costume shop and an alleged “billion dollar cover up.”
Then, according
to Variety, a new documentary
reveals the untold story behind Roger Corman’s notorious never-released Fantastic Four movie. (I’ve seen the new one. It’s only almost
as bad as you’ve
heard.)
Thursday, August 20, 2015
Is it funny because it’s true?
In a recent
article in National Review, Ian
Tuttle tells us that “standup comedy is colliding with progressivism.” He notes that comedians like Jerry Seinfeld
and Gilbert Gottfried have complained of a new political correctness they
perceive in college audiences and in comedy clubs, and he cites feminists and
others who routinely protest against allegedly “sexist,” “racist,” and/or
“homophobic” jokes told by prominent comedians like Louis C. K. In Tuttle’s view, the “pious aspirations” of left-wing
“moral busybodies” have led them to “[object] to humor that does not bolster
their ideology” and “to conflate what is funny with what is acceptable to laugh
at.”
Religion and the Social Sciences
Check out the recently published Religion and the Social Sciences: Conversations with Robert Bellah and Christian Smith, edited by R. R. Reno and Barbara McClay. The volume is a collection of essays presented at two conferences hosted by First Things on the work of Bellah and Smith. (My essay “Natural Theology, Revealed Theology, Liberal Theology” is included.) The publisher’s website for the book can be found here.
Thursday, August 13, 2015
Marriage inflation
When
everyone is somebody, then no one’s anybody.
W. S. Gilbert, The Gondoliers
Lake
Wobegon, where all the women are strong, all the men are good looking, and all
the children are above average.
Garrison Keillor, A Prairie Home Companion
If you printed a lot of extra money and passed it around so as to make
everyone wealthier, the end result would merely be dramatically to decrease the
buying power of money. If you make it
easier for college students to get an “A” grade in their courses, the end
result will be that “A” grades will come to be regarded as a much less reliable
indicator of a student’s true merit. If
you give prizes to everyone who participates in a competition, winning a prize
will cease to be a big deal. In general,
where X is perceived to have greater value than Y and you try to raise the
value of Y by assimilating it to X, the actual result will instead be simply to
lower the value of X to that of Y.
Thursday, August 6, 2015
Unintuitive metaphysics
At Aeon, philosopher
Elijah Millgram comments on metaphysics and the contemporary analytic philosopher’s
penchant for appealing to intuitions. Give it a read -- it‘s very short. Millgram uses an anecdote to illustrate the
point that what intuitively seems to
be an objective fact can sometimes reflect merely contingent “policies we’ve
adopted,” where “the sense of indelible rightness and wrongness comes from
having gotten so very used to those policies.”
And of course, such policies can be bad ones. Hence the dubiousness of grounding
metaphysical arguments in intuition.
Wednesday, July 29, 2015
Empiricism and sola scriptura redux
After my
recent series of long posts on sola
scriptura (here,
here,
and here),
I fear that you, dear reader, may be starting to feel as burned out on the
topic as I do. But one final post is in
order, both because there are a couple of further points I think worth making,
and because Andrew Fulford at The Calvinist International has
now posted a rejoinder to my response to him. And as it happens, what I have to say about
his latest article dovetails somewhat with what I was going to say anyway. (Be warned that the post to follow is pretty
long. But it’s also the last post I hope
to write on this topic for a long while.)
Following
Feyerabend, I’ve been comparing sola
scriptura to early modern empiricism.
Let’s pursue the analogy a little further and consider two specific
parallels between the doctrines. First,
both face a fatal dilemma of being either self-defeating or vacuous. Second, each is committed to a reductionism
which crudely distorts the very epistemic criterion it claims zealously to
uphold. Let’s consider these issues in
turn.
Thursday, July 23, 2015
Fulford on sola scriptura, Part II
Let’s return
to Andrew
Fulford’s reply at The Calvinist International to my
recent post on Feyerabend, empiricism, and sola scriptura. Recall that
the early Jesuit critique of sola scriptura cited by Feyerabend
maintains that (a) scripture alone can never tell you what counts as
scripture, (b) scripture alone cannot tell you how to interpret
scripture, and (c) scripture alone cannot give us a procedure for deriving
consequences from scripture, applying it to new circumstances, etc. In an
earlier post I addressed Fulford’s reply to point (a). Let’s now consider his attempt to rebut the
other two points.
Saturday, July 18, 2015
Fulford on sola scriptura, Part I
At The
Calvinist International, Andrew
Fulford replies to my recent
post on Feyerabend, empiricism, and sola
scriptura. You’ll recall that
the early Jesuit critique of sola
scriptura cited by Feyerabend maintains that (a) scripture alone can never
tell you what counts as scripture, (b) scripture alone cannot tell you
how to interpret scripture, and (c) scripture alone cannot give us a
procedure for deriving consequences from scripture, applying it to new
circumstances, etc. Fulford says that
these objections “essentially rely on a caricature of the teaching,” and offers
responses to each point. Let’s consider
them in order.
Monday, July 13, 2015
Feyerabend on empiricism and sola scriptura
In his essay
“Classical Empiricism,” available in Problems
of Empiricism: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2, philosopher of science Paul
Feyerabend compares the empiricism of the early moderns to the Protestant
doctrine of sola scriptura. He suggests that there are important
parallels between them; in particular, he finds them both incoherent, and for
the same reasons. (No, Feyerabend is not
doing Catholic apologetics. He’s
critiquing empiricism.)
Thursday, July 9, 2015
Aristotle’s four causes versus pantheism
For the Platonist,
the essences or natures of the things of our experience are not in the things
themselves, but exist in the Platonic “third realm.” The essence or nature of a tree, for example,
is not to be looked for in the tree itself, but in the Form of Tree; the
essence of a man is not to be looked for in any human being but rather in the
Form of Man; and so forth. Now, if the
essence of being a tree (treeness, if
you will) is not to be found in a tree, nor the essence of being a man (humanness) in a man, then it is hard to
see how what we ordinarily call a
tree really exists as a tree, or how what
we call a man really exists as a man. Indeed, the trees and men we see are said by
Plato merely imperfectly to “resemble” something else, namely the Forms. So, what we call a tree seems at the end of
the day to be no more genuinely tree-like than a statue or mirror image of a
tree is; what we call a man seems no more genuinely human than a statue or
mirror image of a man is; and so forth.
Monday, July 6, 2015
Caught in the net
Some of the
regular readers and commenters at this blog have started up a Classical Theism,
Philosophy, and Religion discussion forum.
Check it out.
Philosopher
Stephen Mumford brings his Arts Matters blog to an end with a post on why he
is pro-science and anti-scientism.
Then he inaugurates his new blog at Philosophers Magazine with a post on
a
new and improved Cogito argument for the reality of causation.
Speaking of
which: At Aeon, Mathias Frisch discusses
the
debate over causation and physics.
The Guardian asks: Is
Richard Dawkins destroying his reputation?
And at Scientific American,
John Horgan says that biologist
Jerry Coyne’s new book “goes too far” in denouncing religion.
Monday, June 29, 2015
Marriage and The Matrix
Suppose a
bizarre skeptic seriously proposed -- not as a joke, not as dorm room bull
session fodder, but seriously -- that you, he, and everyone else were
part of a computer-generated virtual reality like the one featured in the science-fiction
movie The Matrix. Suppose he easily shot down the arguments you
initially thought sufficient to refute him.
He might point out, for instance, that your appeals to what we know from
common sense and science have no force, since they are (he insists) just part
of the Matrix-generated illusion.
Suppose many of your friends were so impressed by this skeptic’s ability
to defend his strange views -- and so unimpressed by your increasingly flustered
responses -- that they came around to his side.
Suppose they got annoyed with you for not doing the same, and started to
question your rationality and even your decency. Your adherence to commonsense realism in the
face of the skeptic’s arguments is, they say, just irrational prejudice.
Tuesday, June 23, 2015
There’s no such thing as “natural atheology”

[S]ome theologians and theistic
philosophers have tried to give successful arguments or proofs for the existence of God. This
enterprise is called natural theology…
Other philosophers, of course, have presented arguments for the falsehood of theistic beliefs; these philosophers
conclude that belief in God is demonstrably irrational or unreasonable. We might call this enterprise natural
atheology. (pp. 2-3)
Cute,
huh? Actually (and with all due respect
for Plantinga), I’ve always found the expression “natural atheology” pretty
annoying, even when I was an atheist. The
reason is that, given what natural theology as traditionally understood is
supposed to be, the suggestion that there is a kind of bookend subject matter
called “natural atheology” is somewhat inept.
(As we will see, though, Plantinga evidently does not think of natural theology in a traditional way.)
Thursday, June 18, 2015
Love and sex roundup
Here is a roundup of blog posts and other readings on sex, romantic love, and sexual morality as they are understood from a traditional natural law perspective. [It is updated periodically to include more recent relevant posts and articles.]
My essay “In Defense of the Perverted Faculty Argument” appears in my anthology Neo-Scholastic
Essays. It provides a fairly detailed and systematic treatment of the Thomistic natural law foundations of sexual morality. Along the way it criticizes the so-called "New Natural Law" approach.
Monday, June 15, 2015
Cross on Scotus on causal series
Duns Scotus
has especially interesting and important things to say about the distinction
between causal series ordered accidentally and those ordered essentially -- a
distinction that plays a key role in Scholastic arguments for God’s
existence. I discuss the distinction and
Scotus’s defense of it in Scholastic
Metaphysics, at pp. 148-54.
Richard Cross, in his excellent book, Duns
Scotus, puts forward some criticisms of Scotus’s position. I think Cross’s objections fail. Let’s take a look at them.
Wednesday, June 10, 2015
Review of Wilson and Scruton
In
the Spring 2015 issue of the Claremont
Review of Books, I review Edward O. Wilson’s The
Meaning of Human Existence and Roger Scruton’s The
Soul of the World.
Sunday, June 7, 2015
Neo-Scholastic Essays
I am pleased
to announce the publication of Neo-Scholastic
Essays, a collection of previously published academic articles of mine
from the last decade, along with some previously unpublished papers and other
material. Here are the cover copy and
table of contents:
In a series of publications over the
course of a decade, Edward Feser has argued for the defensibility and abiding
relevance to issues in contemporary philosophy of Scholastic ideas and
arguments, and especially of Aristotelian-Thomistic ideas and arguments. This work has been in the vein of what has
come to be known as “analytical Thomism,” though the spirit of the project goes
back at least to the Neo-Scholasticism of the period from the late nineteenth
century to the middle of the twentieth.
Tuesday, June 2, 2015
Religion and superstition
The
Routledge Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, edited by
Graham Oppy, has just been published. My
essay “Religion and Superstition” is among the chapters. The book’s table of contents and other details
can be found here. (The book is very expensive. But I believe you should be able to read all
or most of my essay via the
preview at Google Books.)
Saturday, May 30, 2015
Aristotle watches Blade Runner
You can
never watch Blade Runner too many
times, and I’m due for another viewing.
In D. E. Wittkower’s anthology Philip
K. Dick and Philosophy, there’s an article by Ross Barham which makes
some remarks about the movie’s famous “replicants” and their relationship
to human beings which are interesting though, in my view, mistaken. Barham considers how we might understand the
two kinds of creature in light of Aristotle’s four causes, and suggests that
this is easier to do with replicants than with human beings. This is, I think, the reverse of the
truth. But Barham’s reasons are not hard
to understand given modern assumptions (which Aristotle would reject) about
nature in general and human nature in particular.
Monday, May 25, 2015
D. B. Hart and the “terrorism of obscurantism”
Many years
ago, Steven Postrel and I interviewed
John Searle for Reason magazine. Commenting on his famous dispute with Jacques
Derrida, Searle remarked:
With Derrida, you can hardly misread
him, because he's so obscure. Every time
you say, "He says so and so," he always says, "You misunderstood
me." But if you try to figure out
the correct interpretation, then that's not so easy. I once said this to Michel Foucault, who was
more hostile to Derrida even than I am, and Foucault said that Derrida
practiced the method of obscurantisme terroriste (terrorism of obscurantism). We
were speaking French. And I said,
"What the hell do you mean by that?" And he said, "He writes so obscurely you
can't tell what he's saying, that's the obscurantism part, and then when you
criticize him, he can always say, 'You didn't understand me; you're an idiot.' That's the terrorism part."
Wednesday, May 20, 2015
Stupid rhetorical tricks
In honor of
David Letterman’s final show tonight, let’s look at a variation on his famous
“Stupid pet tricks” routine. It involves
people rather animals, but lots of Pavlovian frenzied salivating. I speak of David Bentley Hart’s latest
contribution, in
the June/July issue of First Things,
to our dispute about whether there will be animals in Heaven. The article consists of Hart (a) flinging
epithets like “manualist Thomism” and “Baroque neoscholasticism” so as to rile
up whatever readers there are who might be riled up by such epithets, while (b)
ignoring the substance of my arguments.
Pretty sad. I reply at Public Discourse.
Tuesday, May 12, 2015
Lewis on transposition
C. S.
Lewis’s essay “Transposition” is available in his collection The
Weight of Glory, and also online here. It is, both philosophically and theologically,
very deep, illuminating the relationship between the material and the
immaterial, and between the natural and the supernatural. (Note that these are different distinctions,
certainly from a Thomistic point of view.
For there are phenomena that are immaterial but still natural. For example, the human intellect is
immaterial, but still perfectly “natural” insofar as it is in our nature to
have intellects. What is “supernatural” is what goes beyond a
thing’s nature, and it is not beyond a thing’s nature to be immaterial if
immateriality just is part of its nature.)
Friday, May 8, 2015
A linkfest
My review of
Charles Bolyard and Rondo Keele, eds., Later
Medieval Metaphysics: Ontology, Language, and Logic appears in the
May 2015 issue of Metaphysica.
At Thomistica.net, Thomist theologian Steven
Long defends
capital punishment against “new natural lawyer” Chris Tollefsen.
In the Journal of the American Philosophical Association,
physicist Carlo Rovelli defends
Aristotle’s physics.
At Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, Christopher
Martin reviews Brian Davies’ Thomas
Aquinas's Summa Theologiae: A Guide and Commentary.
Sunday, May 3, 2015
Animal souls, Part II
Recently,
in First Things, David Bentley Hart criticized
Thomists for denying that there will be non-human animals in Heaven. I responded in an article at Public Discourse and in a
follow-up blog post, defending the view that there will be no such animals
in the afterlife. I must say that some
of the responses to what I wrote have been surprisingly… substandard for
readers of a philosophy blog. A few
readers simply opined that Thomists don’t appreciate animals, or that the
thought of Heaven without animals is too depressing.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)