For example,
suppose we say that God is merciful toward the righteous and takes vengeance on
the wicked. For Maimonides, the right
way to understand this is as saying that God causes the righteous to be
rewarded and the wicked to be punished.
It is a statement about the effects of God’s actions, not about the
divine nature itself. Or suppose we say
that God is omnipotent. For Maimonides,
this should be understood as a statement to the effect that there are in God no
limitations of the kind that constrain the power of created things. It is a statement about the divine nature,
but only about what is not true of
it, rather than a positive attribution.
In his
famous The Guide of the Perplexed,
Maimonides defends Aristotelian arguments for the existence of a divine first
cause. He also defends the doctrine of
divine simplicity, according to which God is in no way composed of parts. It is in light of this fact about the divine
nature, says Maimonides, that we can see that our knowledge of it can only be
negative. He argues as follows:
It has been proved that God exists by necessity and that He
is non-composite… and we can apprehend only that He is, not what He is. It is therefore meaningless that He should
have any positive attribute, since the fact that He is is not something outside
of what He is, so that the attribute might indicate one of these two. Much less can what He is be of a composite
character, so that the attribute could indicate one of the parts. Even less can He be substrate to accidents,
so that the attribute could indicate these.
Thus there is no scope for any positive attributes in any way
whatsoever. (Book I, Chapter LVIII, at
p. 80 of the
abridged Rabin translation)
Let’s unpack
this. In this passage, it seems,
Maimonides tries to show that divine simplicity all by itself entails an
exclusively apophatic theology. How
so? Start with the point he makes in the
middle of the paragraph, concerning the proposal that to speak of a divine
positive attribute “could indicate one of the parts” of God. Obviously this would be ruled out by divine
simplicity, which denies that God has any parts. Nor, as he says at the end of the passage,
could a positive attribute be an accident inhering in the divine substrate,
because divine simplicity also rules out any distinction in God between
substrate and accidents.
The third
option Maimonides considers and rules out is the proposal that a divine
positive attribute might be identifiable with either “the fact that He is” or “what
He is” – that is to say, with either God’s existence or his essence. The idea here seems to be that someone who
thinks we can predicate positive attributes of God might suppose that God’s
existence is a positive attribute distinct from his essence, which we can
predicate of that essence; or that God’s essence is a positive attribute
distinct from his existence, which we can predicate of that existence. And the trouble with this proposal,
Maimonides says, is that given divine simplicity, there is no distinction
between God’s essence and his existence.
They are one and the same thing.
The
argument, then, seems to be that these three proposals would be the only ways
to make sense of positive divine attributes, but all three are ruled out by
divine simplicity; therefore, as he concludes at the end of the passage, “there
is no scope for any positive attributes in any way whatsoever.”
The reader
might wonder, though, exactly why we should regard these three as the only
options. Some remarks Maimonides makes
earlier in Book I of the Guide indicate
the answer. In Chapter LI, he writes:
It is thus evident that an attribute must be one of two
things. Either it is the essence of the
thing to which it is attributed, and thus an explanation of a term… Or the
attribute is different from the thing to which it is attributed, and thus an
idea added to that thing. Consequently
that attribute is an accident of that essence.
(p. 67)
It is not
hard to see why Maimonides would deny that God has attributes in the second
sense, for that would be ruled out by the thesis that there is, given divine
simplicity, no distinction in God between substrate and accidents. But what about attributes in the first sense,
that is to say, an attribute understood as “the essence of the thing to which it is attributed, and thus
an explanation of a term”? And what
exactly does Maimonides mean by this?
He
illustrates the idea with the example of asserting that “Man is a reasoning
animal.” When we predicate of man the
attribute of being a reasoning animal, we are really just picking out the
essence of man, and thereby giving an “explanation of [the] term” (i.e. the
term “man”). The attribute in this case
is nothing different from the essence or nature of the thing to which we are
ascribing the attribute. To predicate of
God a positive attribute in this sense, then, would be to explain the meaning
of “God” by stating the divine essence.
Yet Maimonides says that even here, “this kind of attribute we reject
with reference to God” (p. 67). Why?
The subsequent
chapter of the Guide, Chapter LII,
indicates the reason. Suppose we try to
define God, in something like the way we define man as a reasoning animal. This, Maimonides says, would imply that God
has “pre-existing causes,” which as first cause he cannot have (p. 68). How so?
Maimonides’ meaning here seems to be this. When we define man as a reasoning animal, we
are identifying him as belonging to a certain genus (namely, animal) and as set apart from other
things in that genus by a differentia (namely, reasoning). Now, in a sense,
animality and rationality are thus prior
to man, and thus they are causes, of a sort, of his being. Since God is uncaused, then, he cannot be
defined in terms of a genus and a differentia. (Again, this seems to me to be what Maimonides
is getting at, though he doesn’t spell it out in the relevant passage in
Chapter LII.)
Maimonides
then says that another thing we might be doing when predicating an attribute of
something in the sense of defining it is describing it in terms of part of its essence. We do this, for example, when we say that man is an animal. But this too cannot be what we’re doing in
the case of God, because given divine simplicity, there are no parts to God’s
essence.
Thus does Maimonides
claim to show that we can say nothing positive about the divine nature. But some readers may think he would still
need to say more in order to make the case. And they would be right. For consider Aquinas’s alternative position. Like Maimonides, he strongly affirms divine
simplicity, holds that we cannot strictly define the divine essence, and takes
much of our knowledge of God’s nature to be negative. But he rejects the extreme claim that we can
say nothing positive about him.
Aquinas
argues that Maimonides’ position does not adequately account for talk about
God’s goodness, wisdom, and the like. He notes that the view that attributing goodness to God is really just a way
of saying that God is the cause of good things cannot explain why we say that
God is good but not that God is a physical object – for, after all, God is the
cause of physical objects too. Aquinas
continues:
When we say, “God is good,” the meaning is not, “God is the
cause of goodness,” or “God is not evil”; but the meaning is, “Whatever good we
attribute to creatures, pre-exists in God,” and in a more excellent and higher
way. Hence it does not follow that God
is good, because He causes goodness; but rather, on the contrary, He causes
goodness in things because He is good. (Summa
Theologiae I.13.2)
To be sure,
this is not because there is some common genus to which God and other good
things belong. Nor does Aquinas think we
have a clear idea of the nature of God’s goodness. Nor, given divine simplicity, does he think
that God’s goodness is distinct from his wisdom or his power or any of his
other attributes. Still, when we say
that God is good, we are in Aquinas’s view saying something positive about him,
and something literally true.
How can this
be? The answer has to do with Aquinas’s
famous view that not all literal language is either univocal or equivocal, but
that some is analogical, and that
this is the case with predications of the divine attributes. When we say that God is good, we are not
saying that he is good in exactly the same sense in which we are good (which would
be to use “good” in a univocal way), nor are we saying that he is good in some
completely unrelated sense (which would be to use “good” in an equivocal
way). We are saying that there is
something in God that is analogous to
what we call “goodness” in us, even if it is not exactly the same thing.
Maimonides
would disagree. For him, when we apply
to God’s nature the same terms we use to describe created things, we speak
equivocally. This is true even when we
say that God exists, for God “shares no common trait with anything outside Him
at all, for the term ‘existence’ is only applied to Him as well as to creatures
by way of homonymy and in no other way” (The
Guide of the Perplexed, Book I,
Chapter LII, at p. 70).
This is not
a dispute I will explore here. Suffice
it for present purposes to note that while Maimonides writes as if the controversy
over whether God has positive attributes hinges on whether or not one accepts
divine simplicity, that is not in fact the case. Rather, it hinges on whether or not one
accepts that we can truly speak of God in analogical terms.
Related
posts:
Dharmakīrti
and Maimonides on divine action
Fascinating post, Ed.
ReplyDeleteI think that Maiomonades did not appreciate the subtle middle ground between univocal and equivocal in the same way as Aquinas did -- and that must be one of the reasons he's so rigid in his position about the negative approach to God.