Here is a summary of her position. The pacifist holds that all killing is immoral, even when necessary to protect citizens against criminal evildoers within a nation, or foreign adversaries without. This position is contrary to the basic precondition of any social order, which is the right to protect itself against attempts to destroy it. It also has no warrant in the orthodox Christian tradition. A less extreme but related error is the thesis that violence can never justly be initiated, but at most can only ever be justified in response to those who have initiated it. In fact, Anscombe argues, what matters is not who strikes the first blow, but who is in the right. For example, it was in her judgment right for the British to initiate violence in order to suppress chattel slavery.
That is one
set of errors. But another and opposite
extreme error is to abuse the principle that war can sometimes be justifiable,
in order to try to rationalize violence that is in fact unjust. Indeed, this opposite extreme is, in
Anscombe’s view, the more common error. And
it is more common in war than in police activity, because war affords more occasions
for the evil of killing the innocent, and civilians in particular. The principle of double effect is too often
misapplied in attempts to rationalize such killing.
Having given
a general description of these two sorts of error, Anscombe then goes on to
examine each in more detail. She
suggests that in the early twentieth century, some were drawn to pacifism in
part as an overreaction to universal conscription (which she regards as an
evil). But her main focus is on the
theme that pacifism derives from a distortion of Christianity. In part this has to do with a hostility to
the ethos of the Old Testament, which she argues is widely misunderstood and
widely and wrongly thought to be at odds with the New Testament. But the New Testament too has been badly
misunderstood. For example, counsels to
which only some are called (such as
giving away one’s worldly goods) are sometimes misrepresented as precepts
binding on all.
“The truth
about Christianity,” Anscombe says, “is that it is a severe and practicable
religion, not a beautifully ideal but impracticable one” (p. 48). But the distortions she describes have made
Christianity seem to be an ideal but
impracticable one. And the attraction
some Christians have for pacifism is an example. Many Christians and non-Christians alike
believe the falsehood that Christ calls us all to pacifism. And because no society could survive if it
practiced pacifism, many thus conclude that Christian morality is simply not
practical.
Here, as
Anscombe argues, is where pacifism inadvertently paves the way for those who
rationalize the murder of the innocent. Falsely
supposing that all violence is evil
and also noting that violence is necessary to preserve a society against
evildoers, they take the short step to the conclusion that “committed to
‘compromise with evil,’ one must go the whole hog and wage war à outrance” (p. 48). In other words, once we are convinced that
we’re going to have to do evil anyway in order to protect society, there’s no
limit to the evil we will rationalize as necessary to achieve this good
end. Unrealistic moralizing has as its
sequel an amoral realpolitik, falsely
presenting itself as the only alternative.
With
Catholics, Anscombe says, this amorality masquerades as an application of the
principle of double effect. True, this
principle can indeed in some cases justify actions that foreseeably risk harm
to civilians, when that harm is not intended and when it is not out of
proportion to the good to be achieved.
(For example, it can be justifiable to bomb an enemy military base even
if one foresees, while not intending, that some civilians nearby could be
killed as a result.)
The trouble,
Anscombe says, is that people often play fast and loose with the notion of
“intention” in order to abuse the principle of double effect. For example, it would be sheer sophistry for
an employee to say that when he helped his boss embezzle from the company, his
“intention” was not really to assist
in embezzlement, but only to avoid getting fired, so that the action could be
justified by double effect. Similarly,
Anscombe argues, it is sophistry to pretend that the obliteration bombing of
cities does not involve any intentional killing of civilians, but only the
intention to end a war earlier. Another
sophistry involves interpreting what counts as a “combatant” very broadly, so
as to try to justify attacks on the civilian population in general. Anscombe also responds to various other attempts
to rationalize violations of just war criteria.
That, again,
is the argument in outline. Here are
some ways it is relevant today. We have,
on the one hand, some Catholics who appear at least to flirt with pacifism. Pope Francis said things that implied that
war could never be just and that traditional teaching on this matter needed to
be rethought, though he
also said things that pointed in the other direction. As with other topics, his teaching on this
matter was simply muddled rather than a clear departure from tradition. But it was muddled in a way that gives aid
and comfort to the first, pacifistic erroneous extreme identified by Anscombe.
On the other
hand, we also have many who go to the opposite extreme criticized by Anscombe,
of trying to rationalize unjust harm to civilian populations by abuse of the
principle of double effect and related sophistries. For example, this is the case with much of
the commentary on Israel’s war in Gaza. Israel
certainly had the right and indeed the duty to retaliate for the diabolical
Hamas attack of October 7, 2023, which killed almost 1,200 people. But many seem to think that this gives Israel
a blank check to do whatever it likes in Gaza, or at least whatever it likes
short of deliberately targeting civilians.
That is not
the case. Yes, traditional just war doctrine
holds that it is always immoral deliberately to kill civilians. But that is by no means all that it says on
the matter. It also holds that it is
immoral deliberately to destroy civilian property and infrastructure, and
thereby to make normal civilian life impossible. To be sure, it holds too that it can, by the
principle of double effect, sometimes be permissible to carry out military
actions that put civilian lives and property at risk, where such risk is not intended but simply foreseen. But it also holds that this harm must not be out of proportion to the
good that one hopes to secure by way of such military action.
Throughout
Gaza, however, civilian property and infrastructure have been largely destroyed,
and ordinary life made impossible. The resulting
humanitarian crisis has been steadily worsening. Casualty numbers in Gaza are hotly disputed,
but they are undeniably high. According to
a recent report:
Almost 84,000 people died in Gaza between October 2023 and
early January 2025 as a result of the Hamas-Israel war, estimates the first
independent survey of deaths. More than
half of the people killed were women aged 18-64, children or people over 65,
reports the study.
Suppose for the
sake of argument that the true number is half of that, or even just one third
of that. That would still be extremely
high. Such loss of life, destruction of
basic infrastructure, and making of ordinary civilian life impossible are out
of proportion to the evil Israel is retaliating against. And this is putting aside the awful
conditions under which Gazans have been living for years, and the allegations
of cases where civilians have been deliberately targeted during the current
war. These too are hotly disputed
matters, but the point is that even if we
don’t factor them in, Israeli action in Gaza seems clearly disproportionate
and thus not justifiable by the principle of double effect.
There is
also the sophistry some commit of pretending that if a civilian sympathizes
with Hamas, he is morally on a par with a combatant and may be treated as such. And then there is the proposal some
have made to dispossess the Gazans altogether, which would only add a further,
massive layer of injustice.
None of this can facilitate a long-term solution to the Israel-Palestine problem, but will inevitably greatly inflame further already high hostility against Israel. A commitment to preserving the basic preconditions of ordinary civilian life for Israelis and Palestinians alike is both morally required by just war criteria, and a precondition to any workable modus vivendi.
I hold great respect for Ed, but unfortunately, and despite a number of good points, he leans toward the same error here as Miss Anscombe did in her essay; namely, a definition of “evil” that’s a little pat. That’s hardly to say that either is “wrong,” but it’s to suggest that they don’t grapple with the realities of combat on the ground. Anscombe was certainly correct to say that the use of nuclear weapons was morally wrong, but her proposed solution (a negotiated peace with Japan) does not take adequate account of the strategic ramifications of such a move.
ReplyDeleteAt least Anscombe had the benefit of being right about the wrongness of using the Bomb. Ed here makes an, if he’ll allow me, elementary error about disproportion in casualties. As many actual just war ethicists (e.g., Lord Biggar in the UK) will note, “proportionality” is only a “prudential” criterion in the tradition, precisely because it is so difficult to accurately predict what will or won’t be proportionate.
For example, one could easily have predicted that the devastation necessary to obtain the surrender of Japan after Pearl Harbor would be “disproportionate” - hundreds of thousands, if not millions of civilians would need to die to vindicate the deaths of only a few thousand Americans. But that “disproportion” by no means vitiated the justice of the American cause, nor did it render the decision for war ultimately disproportionate.
In a similar way, Israel is responding to perhaps the worst terror attack in history, with the aim of preventing future acts of violence (an inevitability if Hamas remains in power) and with liberating the population of Gaza from terrorist rule. Anyone could have predicted that civilian casualties would be great. But that fact in itself (and apart from any particular acts which may be judged to have violated the laws of war) - especially in light of the relatively low civilian-to-combatant kill ratio - does not render the continuation of the Israeli campaign immoral, just as it did not render immoral the American decision to pursue unconditional surrender in WWII.
'Traditional just war doctrine holds that it is always immoral deliberately to kill civilians. But that is by no means all that it says on the matter. It also holds that it is immoral deliberately to destroy civilian property and infrastructure, and thereby to make normal civilian life impossible.' This is not the case. If it were, just war theory would be substantially equivalent to pacifism, because it is impossible to wage war without choosing to destroy civilian property and infrastructure. Anscombe's article was aimed at the use of nuclear weapons and the bombing attacks on civilians in the Second World War; that is, on military measures that took as their goal the killing of vast amounts of civilians. That is not relevant to Israeli military actions in Gaza, which have the goal of destroying a military and terrorist threat (Hamas) and rescuing Israeli hostages. You assert that 'Such loss of life, destruction of basic infrastructure, and making of ordinary civilian life impossible are out of proportion to the evil Israel is retaliating against. And this is putting aside the awful conditions under which Gazans have been living for years.' Since Hamas is in control of Gaza and has been for years, the awful conditions there are the responsibility of Hamas and provide a reason for Israeli attacks on that organisation. The claims that Gaza was besieged by the Israelis are false; the area had functioning ports and airports that operated freely with the rest of the world, and Gazans were able to work in Israel. It was an open-air prison only to the extent that it suffered from the tyrannical and criminal rule of Hamas. The Hamas organisation received large amounts of money - more than a billion dollars a year - which it spent on weapons and tunnel systems rather than the Gazans. The destruction of civilian infrastructure in Gaza is a result of Hamas's policy of deliberately using civilians and civilian institutions such as hospitals as military installations and human shields. This destruction is thus the fault of Hamas rather than the Israelis. You assert without any justification that the damage and loss of life in Gaza is 'out of proportion to the evil Israel is retaliating against'. The characterisation of Israeli actions as 'retaliation' is tendentious and false. These actions are aimed at destroying Hamas and rescuing hostages. Hamas is a jihadi terror organisation that has as its immediate goal the destruction of Israel and the killing of all Israeli Jews; its further goals are the destruction of Christianity and of Christians who will not convert to Islam. It indoctrinates all the inhabitants of Gaza in its satanic ideology and kills anyone who questions it. It is part of a broader jihadi movement that is a threat to all European, African and Middle Eastern Christians, and that is currently massacring Christians throughout Africa and the Middle East. Its destruction is a very important and just military objective, and Israeli actions in Gaza - which it should be noted promise to free the Gazans from the evils of Hamas rule - are entirely justified and proportionate.
ReplyDeleteIt seems that all the church fathers who wrote on this relevant topic during the first 300 years taught this version of pacifism: correct for kings and govt to use the sword (God ordained these worldly authorities to restraint evil) while wrong for any Christian to kill any fellow human being. Hence those church fathers wrote against Christians taking up any job that involved killing human beings.
ReplyDeleteSeparately, regarding selling possessions to give to the poor with the result that one would then have treasure in heaven: this commandment was given not only to some Christians but to all the disciples in Luke 12.33-34. And then in Luke 14.33 Jesus was declaring to the crowd: “any one of you who does not give up all his possessions cannot be my disciple.” (See the Greek text: the word “possessions” is there)
johannes