“The book's title is an homage to David Hume, and Feser has certainly taken Hume to task, giving cogent arguments for the reality of the self (chapter 2), freedom of the will (chapter 4), immateriality of the intellect (chapter 8), and more…
It is with contemporary developments in the philosophy of mind where Feser is at his best, and readers will not be disappointed with his critique of positions such as Buddhism's no-self doctrine (chapter 2)…
Feser again is at his best in cogently establishing the immateriality of the intellect. He puts forth various arguments. His most powerful argument is a modified version of James Ross's argument from the indeterminacy of the physical (chapter 8)… One of the unique contributions that Feser makes to contemporary literature is his defense of the immateriality of the intellect from its simplicity (chapter 8). Readers should pay close attention to this powerful argument.”
End quote. Boczar also
offers two lines of criticism. First, he
suggests that I could say more to explain how disembodied human souls are
individuated after death. He notes that
I hold, as Aquinas does, that the fact that they were associated with distinct
bodies before death is
sufficient to individuate them. However,
says Boczar, “this should be spelled out more, as it is well known that the Latin
Averroists at Paris held that the individual ceases to exist after death, even
though the intellect is immaterial and immortal.”
This is a
view Aquinas addressed in several places, and the philosophical anthropology he
appealed to in answering it is essentially the same as the one I defend in the
book. Start with the fact that any two
human beings, such as Socrates and Plato, are distinct substances of the kind rational animal. Part of what this entails is that they are
not fewer than two substances. When Socrates walks or talks and Plato walks
or talks, there are two numerically distinct things carrying out two
numerically distinct activities. There
is Socrates and his walking, and Plato and his walking. And there is Socrates and his talking, and
Plato and his talking. There is not
somehow one substance here that is doing all the walking and talking. We know this from experience, as surely as we
know from experience that two trees or two stones are numerically distinct things
with numerically distinct properties.
Another part
of what it entails is that Socrates and Plato are not more than two substances.
With Socrates, for example, it is one and the same substance that both
walks and talks. It is not that Socrates
is an aggregate of two substances, one which does the walking and one which
does the talking. Now, as a rational
animal, among the many other things a human being like Socrates does are
thinking, willing, seeing, hearing, thirsting, and digesting. And again, it is one and the same substance
that does all of these things. This too
we know from experience, as surely as we know in the case of a tree or a stone
that it is one and the same substance that does the things characteristic of
the tree and that has the properties characteristic of a stone.
What these
facts rule out are, first, the Averroist view that it is a single, common
intellectual substance that is really doing all the things of an intellectual kind
that we attribute to different human beings; and, second, the Cartesian view
that there are, in the case of any human being, two substances doing what human
beings do, a res cogitans doing the intellectual
things and a res extensa doing the
corporeal things. Contra the Averroist,
there are as many distinct substances with intellects as there are human
beings. Contra the Cartesian, each of these
substances not only does intellectual things but also bodily things like
walking, seeing, and digesting.
Now, on
Aquinas’s account, matter individuates members of a species, so that the fact
that there are distinct bodies associated with different human beings suffices
to make them distinct individual members of the same species rational animal. But because the intellectual powers are
incorporeal, each individual member of this particular species can carry on
after the death of the body, as an incomplete substance whose operations are reduced
to those of its intellectual powers.
Why, Boczar
wonders, wouldn’t the fact that they can carry on after death make them comparable
to angels, each of whom is the unique member of its own species? The answer is that it is normal for an angel
to be disembodied, but not normal for
a human being to be disembodied. An
angelic intellect without a body is nevertheless a complete substance, but a
human intellect without a body is not
a complete substance. Even when it
persists beyond the death of its body, it is by nature ordered to its body, whereas an angelic intellect is in no way
ordered to a body.
Boczar
overlooks this natural ordering. He
notes that I hold that “the fact that all human beings start out with distinct
bodies is sufficient to individuate them,” but wonders why this would be sufficient.
This would indeed be a mystery if the intellect were related to the body
the way the Cartesian supposes, because that sort of relationship is entirely
contingent. But again, the intellect is
not related to the body in that way. It
is not a complete substance that is only contingently related to (some distinct
substance with) corporeal powers; rather, the intellect is an incorporeal power
of a substance which in its complete state also has corporeal powers.
The other
part of Immortal Souls that Boczar
takes issue with is my discussion of the fixity of the will after death. Like Aquinas, I argue that while the ultimate
end toward which the will is oriented is not fixed while the intellect is
embodied, it becomes fixed with the loss of the body at death. Why, Boczar wonders, would it not become
changeable again when the body is restored at the resurrection?
Here it
seems to me that Boczar has not paid sufficient attention to the details of my
discussion of this issue. As I argue in
my New Blackfriars article “Aquinas on the
Fixity of the Will After Death” and repeat in chapter 10 of Immortal Souls, it is not embodiment as such that entails the changeability
of the will. What is going on is,
rather, this. An end can be changed only
by reference to some further end. For
example, if my goal is to get from Los Angeles to San Francisco as efficiently
as possible and I intend to buy a train ticket in order to realize this end, I
might change my mind and go by airplane instead if I find that that would be a
more efficient way to realize it. And if
my reason for wanting to get to San Francisco is that I believe that an
American Catholic Philosophical Association meeting is being held there, I
might change my mind about going to San Francisco if I find out that my belief
was mistaken and that the meeting is actually going to be in San Diego.
But when we
come to the ultimate end toward which
all my actions are ordered (whatever it might be), that cannot be changed,
precisely because it is ultimate. There
is, in the nature of the case, no higher end by reference to which it might be changed. Now, in the case of an angel, its highest end
is fixed immediately after its creation.
Its will comes to be ordered most fundamentally to whatever its
intellect first judges to be the highest good, and anything else it might will
ever afterward will be willed only insofar as it conduces to that perceived highest
good. That perceived highest good cannot
itself be changed, because there is nothing higher by reference to which it
might be changed.
The reason
this does not happen immediately upon the creation of a human being does indeed
have crucially to do with the body, but not quite in the way Boczar (like many other
readers of Aquinas) supposes. Because
human beings are embodied, they, unlike angels, have passions and sensory appetites
that influence the will in a way that prevents it from becoming fixed on any
particular end as highest. It is only when
these passions and sensory appetites disappear with the death of the body that
the will, now relevantly like that of an angel (insofar as it is free of these
distracting influences), becomes fixed on a perceived highest end. And as with an angel, once this happens, there
is no way for that end to be changed, for in the nature of the case there is no
higher end by reference to which it might be changed.
As others do
when first becoming familiar with this position, Boczar wonders why the
restoration of the body at the resurrection would not open the door to this
perceived highest end being changed. The
mistake they are making is that they suppose that Aquinas’s claim is that, though
the will can become fixed on some ultimate end during a human being’s lifetime,
the body makes it possible for it to become unfixed from that end and fixed
instead on some other ultimate end. And
in that case, why wouldn’t the restoration of the body allow it once again to
become unfixed?
But that is
not what is going on at all. It’s not
that, during life, the presence of the body allows the will successively to become
fixed on different ultimate ends. Rather,
the presence of the body prevents it
from ever becoming fixed on any
ultimate end. The will, while the body
is present, is not like an arrow that reaches a target but can somehow be
removed from that target and fired at another.
Rather, it is like an arrow that has not yet reached any target at
all. The target is reached only at
death. But it is reached then. That is
why restoring the body would in no way allow the will to change its ultimate
end. It could do so only if the will
were still at that point like an arrow that had not yet reached any target.
To take a
different analogy, the will before the death of the body is like wet clay that
is being molded into a series of successive shapes but has not yet fixed on any
of them. Death is like the furnace that
dries the clay into some one determinate shape, such as a pot. Once that happens, the clay cannot ever again
take on any other shape. And in the same
way, once the will has at last fixed on some ultimate end at death, it cannot
become fixed on another, no matter what happens. To ask “Why wouldn’t the restoration of the
body allow the ultimate end to be changed?” is like asking “Why wouldn’t pouring
some water into the pot make the clay once again malleable?”
This, in any event, is what I would say is the correct way to understand Aquinas’s position, or at least what he should say given the relevant principles he is reasoning from. Naturally, there is much more to be said, and I address the subject in detail in Immortal Souls (and I have more to say about the exegetical issues surrounding the relevant texts from Aquinas in the New Blackfriars article).
Insightful points Prof,
ReplyDeleteI recently saw your post on Twitter with regards to how closely you follow Aquinas, I do sometimes bring up questions on Aquinas while commenting here, But I hope you know that it's all in good spirit. I think you are one of the best expositors of Aquinas on the planet and I owe a lot to you. And I admire your commitment to Truth. I don't mean any ill will whatsoever and if you have noticed I am always willing to change my stance where we disagree.
Cheers
Norm
That was a good response to the criticism or perhaps better said as a good clarification.
ReplyDeleteI would like to see how the account of Lazarus and other miraculous resuscitations throughout history would square with this doctrine on the post-mortem fixity of the will. They seem to provide counterexamples to this view.
ReplyDeleteIf Lazarus was genuinely raised from the dead, was his will still fixed, despite being raised back to his fallen body marred with concupiscence? And it’s compounded by the notion that he was in the Limbo of the Fathers after his first death, so his ‘arrow’ already reached his ‘target’ in that sense. So did he live a perfectly virtuous life after being raised? With no bodily passions at all?
What about the case (which admittedly may be just a legend) of the guy that St. Stanislaus raised during a property dispute? According to the story, the man begged to return to Purgatory because he was afraid he might mortally sin and then lose his salvation. I don’t think a departed soul would be ignorant of the fact that his choice is fixed. I’m sure there are other historical examples that may present difficulties like this for the Thomistic story. How would you reconcile them?
I think the difference would be that these men weren't in Heaven or Hell, but I am not sure.
DeleteThat's a good question. Seem like there is a difference between a person's will being fixed on an ultimate end and a person being perfectly virtuous without any bodily passions.
DeleteAquinas, for example, notes that "when the soul is so disordered by sin as to turn away from its last end, viz. God, to Whom it is united by charity, there is mortal sin; but when it is disordered without turning away from God, there is venial sin." In other words, only mortal sin involves a person changing their "ultimate end" from God to something else.
Putting that together with what Feser is arguing here, it would seem that Lazarus could sin venially after his resurrection, but not mortally. At death his will was forever fixed on God as his final end. However, upon his resurrection he might sin venially due to concupiscence or culpable ignorance.
That's different than the state of human beings after the final resurrection, where they have bodies without concupiscence and (more importantly) the beatific vision. Seems like those additional factors combine with the fixity of the will to prevent humans from committing both mortal and venial sins after the final resurrection.
"Aquinas, for example, notes that "when the soul is so disordered by sin as to turn away from its last end, viz. God, to Whom it is united by charity, there is mortal sin; but when it is disordered without turning away from God, there is venial sin." In other words, only mortal sin involves a person changing their "ultimate end" from God to something else."
DeleteI don't know, Jordan. That sounds like the "fundamental option" position, which is contrary to what moral theologians like May, Lawler, and Grisez have commented on and with what JP2 taught.
https://www.hprweb.com/2016/04/the-fundamental-option/
Grisez goes into this more deeply in his "Way of the Lord Jesus", his 3 Vol. study of Moral Theology that is available online/
http://twotlj.org/G-1-16-B.html
Hi MJR,
DeleteThanks for the response and the link. I'm not familiar with the thinkers you cite, but I'll do my best to lay out the distinction as I understand it after a bit of reading.
In Veritatis Splendor, St. Pope John Paul II criticizes the idea that a person's "fundamental option" for or against God as his final end is somehow separate from that person's actual moral choices. According to this (incorrect) logic, a person could "continue to be morally good, persevere in God's grace, and attain salvation, even if certain of his specific kinds of behavior were deliberately and gravely contrary to God's commandments as set forth by the Church." For example, a person might knowingly and willfully commit adultery, and yet not lose sanctifying grace. The pope says this is false and reaffirms the traditional mortal / venial distinction that Aquinas holds.
Applying this to the Lazarus scenario, I think the "fundamental option"-ist would hold that Lazarus could, say, murder someone and yet not lose his salvation. His fundamental option was fixed on God after death. And since the fundamental option is the only thing that matters, separate from any concrete act, nothing he does in his resurrected life could change it.
But that's false. Instead, because Lazarus's will is fixed on God as his final end, he simply will not commit murder. He will always choose not to commit mortal sin. But this same fixed will does not prevent him from criticizing Martha for not adding enough salt to their dinner, for example, since the latter act is a venial sin.
Peaceful days,
Jordan
That sounds like the "fundamental option" position, which is contrary to what moral theologians like May, Lawler, and Grisez have commented on and with what JP2 taught.
DeleteThis overstates the case. What St. Thomas is teaching here is standard fare: every mortal sin - of every kind - is mortal precisely in virtue of involving a will that is concretely determined on an end in a way that wholly excludes God. This does not, however, require that the will chooses a something else in terms of being explicitly aware and explicitly selecting "no, not God at all, but this other good alone". It is sufficient, for example, for the person to be aware that the choice is contrary to God's will and a grave matter. It can be a choice toward a sexual good entailed in a concrete act of adultery, recognized as directly contrary to the 6th commandment, without being thought or expressed as "by choosing this I hereby reject and depart from God forever as my ultimate goal" or anything of the sort. It is in the matter itself being grave that it is impossible for the will to choose it while retaining God as his ultimate end, even though the rejection of God therein is implicit. There is no representation that one's moral status in relation to God sits at some other (deeper) level than the moral status of the grave act of sin which you chose in a concrete act of adultery known as grave and contrary to the 6th commandment.
Jordan
DeleteYes do read Germain Geisez's 3 vol. tome on moral theology, free online. I once heard him say at a lecture, in response to a question about the "fundamental option," that people can and do fall in and of grace and commit mortal sin, even if they are trying to live moral lives. He said that was why frequent confession and communion were important. Happy New Year.
Disembodiment- Fixation of will- intellect knows the greatest good and will is oredered towards the greatest good. You are dead to sin.
DeleteEbodied life- Fundamental option - intellect believe the greatest good and tries to order towards the belief.
Reembodiemnt with corruptable body-life of Jesus earthly life. Ordered to highest good and dead to sin. But would have to suffer in the body for it.
I have some questions about both of your responses.
ReplyDeleteFirst, about individuating disembodied human souls.
"Even when [a human intellect] persists beyond the death of its body, it is by nature ordered to its body, whereas an angelic intellect is in no way ordered to a body."
"...the [human] intellect is an incorporeal power of a substance which in its complete state also has corporeal powers."
If humans are individuated by their bodies, while angels don't need bodies to be individuated, and then humans lose their individuating principle, what is left to individuate them other than a body they no longer enliven (outside of considering them separate species like angels)? I would think there'd have to be some persisting trait in the soul that accounts for the fact that their separated body can still have the final say in which particular soul they are, if that makes sense.
----------
In light of your explanation of the fixity of the will after death due to there being no higher end, I don't understand why the passions of the body are relevant. Or vice versa. Can you help me understand what I'm missing or misunderstanding?
I understand you to mean that any end that is a means to a further end can be swapped with a different end. But the ultimate end is not a means to a further end - it is the final end. Election of a final end does not entail deliberation over its relative conduciveness toward some further end, but rather, deliberation over whether or not it is the highest good. But what aid in THAT deliberation are passions and sensory appetites (among other things), because those are attractions toward alternative ends which all compete for your ultimate allegiance. Angels merely have intellectual reasons, which don't change, but humans have bodily reasons in addition, which do change.
But what causes the angel or disembodied human to "lock in" on the ultimate end such that a new body couldn't reopen the deliberation? It can't merely be the lack of further ends, because that fact did not prevent the body from changing it the first time, which means lack of further ends was not enough to fix it alone. There must be something else that causes the unchangeable effect. Is there some further power or tendency at play?
Alternatively, if lack of further ends DOES result in angels and disembodied humans to "lock in," it would also result in bodied humans locking in. In this case, I don't think you've sufficiently explained how the passions and appetites can prevent this.
"Because human beings are embodied, they, unlike angels, have passions and sensory appetites that influence the will in a way that prevents it from becoming fixed on any particular end as highest."
Why do angels and disembodied humans become fixed on an ultimate end? And what is this "way" you refer to that can somehow prevent it? If your account of why an ultimate end can be "fixed" is that there is no further end, then it would seem that the body has no faculty that would be able to prevent this fixation, because having no further end than your ultimate end is a universal circumstance, for any creature with intellect and will (angel or human; alive or disembodied). If your account of the way passions and sensory appetites influence the will is not frustrated by the fact that the ultimate end has no further ends, then it would seem that you haven't provided a relevant explanation as to why a restored body wouldn't successfully provide the same influences.
In other words, the implication of each of your points seem to contradict each other:
A: Having no further ends causes ultimate end's fixation (implying nothing can ever change it, even first body)
B: Passions and appetites can change ultimate end (implying it can change for a time, despite no further ends)
How do you reconcile the two? Either having no further ends causes fixation, in which case the body seems irrelevant; or the body can swap the ultimate end, in which case having no further ends seems irrelevant.
while angels don't need bodies to be individuated,
DeleteThis is inaptly put: angels "don't need" bodies, precisely because they are not distinguished / separated from others of like kind in the manner of bodies. They are distinguished by principles of differentiation, at the species level, there AREN'T any angels "of like kind" because they each are a different species.
and then humans lose their individuating principle, what is left to individuate them other than a body they no longer enliven (outside of considering them separate species like angels)?
The dead human doesn't "lose" the body in the sense of ceasing to be "a bodily KIND of being" (as angels are not bodily kinds of beings), they have a separation in that the soul ceases to be the animating principle of their body. That soul, caused to become individuated (at conception) by concrete matter, retains its ordination to that concrete matter, and thus retains its individuation also. Death doesn't unravel the individuation that occurred at conception, the soul once individuated is always an individual substantial soul.
I would think there'd have to be some persisting trait in the soul that accounts for the fact that their separated body can still have the final say in which particular soul they are,
Correct: the soul's ordination to that body which first individuated it.
CaptainCH
ReplyDeleteYou raise an interesting point regarding Lazarus. I do hope Dr. Feser will find the time to respond.
Because human beings are embodied, they, unlike angels, have passions and sensory appetites that influence the will in a way that prevents it from becoming fixed on any particular end as highest. It is only when these passions and sensory appetites disappear with the death of the body that the will, now relevantly like that of an angel (insofar as it is free of these distracting influences), becomes fixed on a perceived highest end. And as with an angel, once this happens, there is no way for that end to be changed,
ReplyDeleteI have two questions about this. First, it is clear from other usage that what you must mean by "fixed" is "immutable". However, a potential source of muddle about the preliminary point, that during ordinary life, a human being's body and passions are a reason the will is "not fixed" is an equivocal sense of "fixed" as meaning simply having X as an ultimate end. An ordinary person who was baptized as a child and then reaches the age of reason without committing a mortal sin specifically has God as his ultimate end. That's what it means to be at the age of reason: you are now capable of reasoning to your ultimate end, and willing it. If you went through that process and did not sin, you had to have chosen / willed God as your ultimate end. In that state, your will is set upon a final end. Having sanctifying grace and the theological virtue of charity, this condition is a virtue, i.e. a habit, a condition that persists until acted upon by the will to deliberately change it. This is a DIFFERENT sense of "fixed." Are you sure you didn't involve this anywhere?
But (as we all know) humans in ordinary life are capable of changing their minds and sinning, you could remove your choice of God as your final end and settle on something else, e.g. wealth or pleasure. Thus what was a settled (habitual) condition is not an immutable condition.
Prof, you have not here made clear why the body and passions make the will unable to be fixed in the immutable sense, and (vice versa) why it is that without them the will not only can be fixed in the immutable sense, but that this WILL happen. I offer a possible objection to the latter: suppose that upon death, it is in the ordinary course of things for a human undergoing judgment, their will then becomes immutably fixed. But that it is merely the "ordinary course" of things at the Individual Judgment, it is not a metaphysical necessity that immediately upon death, there is no possibility OTHER than that the will become fixed immutably. Suppose rather that, for those few persons God knows will be sent back to Earth, He declines to judge and interposes an EXTRAordinary course which prevents their will from becoming fixed immutably. This would imply that when they do regain an ordinary life, they can still have a will not immutably fixed on one end.
It is not clear why, given that the supposed dead human whose soul is ordered to a body, TO WHICH THEIR SOUL WILL BE RESTORED, would necessarily be in the same status as angels vis-a-vis "not having sensory appetites that prevents it from becoming fixed". Yes, they don't have the appetites operative right now, but they DO have the appetitive faculties (which angels don't have) and they do have an ordination to be restored to that body to be operative faculties (which angels do not have).
I think there are more steps made to clarify the argument, and unless there is some metaphysical principle involved that I haven't seen yet, God could simply STEP IN and prevent the will from becoming fixed (for those who are going to be sent back).
Some good questions have been asked but I doubt if Dr. Feser has the time to respond , especially with New Years Day coming tomorrow.
DeleteIt seems there is a distinction between our present mortal bodies and our glorified bodies at the resurrection. And so there is perhaps a difference between what we can expect of ourselves and the rare cases when people are restored to their original mortal bodies.
DeleteIt's an interesting speculation regarding Lazarus though. Tradition has it that he traveled with his sisters and was an early bishop before finally passing away.
If you do a Google search you will find that many books have been written on this topic.
ReplyDeleteOne of the most interesting and thorough examinations of this topic is titled Science of Soul ATMA-VIJNANA A Practical Exposition of Ancient Method of Visualization of Soul by Swami Yogeshwaranand Saraswati Ji Maharaj.
It is based on his direct experience of what he writes about and numerous illustrations in support of his understanding.
In this book you nowhere address the forceful critique that Antonio Ramos Díaz has presented against your reading of James F. Ross (both in his 2019 PhD thesis and 2022 paper). His PhD thesis is available here: https://lirias.kuleuven.be/retrieve/528473
ReplyDelete