I appreciate their civility, and Fastiggi’s call at the end of the interview for charity in dealing with those who disagree. But their attempt fails. Much of what Fastiggi has to say are reheated claims that I have already refuted in past exchanges with him, such as the two-part essay I wrote in response to his series on the death penalty at Where Peter Is. (You can find it here and here. The essay was reprinted as a single long article in Ultramontanism and Tradition, edited by Peter Kwasniewski.) Fastiggi simply repeats his assertions without acknowledging, much less answering, my rebuttals. He also makes some new claims, which are no more plausible than the older ones. Let’s take a look.
A straw man
In any
fruitful discussion of this topic, it must constantly be kept in mind that there
are two questions that need to be clearly distinguished. First, is the death penalty intrinsically
wrong? And second, even if it is not
intrinsically wrong, is it nevertheless morally better never to resort to
it? To answer “Yes” to the first
question is to say that capital punishment of
its very nature, and regardless of the circumstances, is wrong, and thus
can never even in principle be used. But
someone could answer “No” to the first question and still answer “Yes” to the
second. To take this view is to say that
while in theory the death penalty could be justified in certain circumstances,
in practice those circumstances never obtain, at least not today, and that the
moral considerations that tell against its use outweigh those that speak in
favor of it.
People who
comment on the topic of Catholicism and capital punishment very frequently
ignore this distinction. The result is
that they often talk past one another and the discussion generates more heat
than light. Now, at the beginning of
their conversation, Fastiggi and Sonna are, to their credit, careful to note
the distinction. But unfortunately, later
in their discussion, they ignore it, and this leads them to attack a straw man.
In
particular, Fastiggi claims (after the 35 minute mark in the video) that “people
say, well, the Church has always taught, always allowed for the [death penalty].” Arguing against this, Fastiggi cites some
Fathers of the Church who were against capital punishment, and concludes that “it’s
almost like a myth, this 2,000 year old tradition, but if it’s repeated enough
by commentators and writers, then people begin to believe it.” Similarly, Sonna remarks (around the 45
minute mark) that “a lot of people have this impression that the Church, as if
it were this uniform block, this constant unchanging permanent wall, has just
consistently said the death penalty’s fine, you know, go ahead and do it.” But in fact, he continues, “historically,
there was an uneasiness at times with the death penalty.” Fastiggi and Sonna make a big deal out of this
theme, as if it is a damning point against Catholic defenders of the death
penalty.
But not so
fast. For here too we need to
distinguish two claims, namely:
(1) The
Church always taught for 2,000 years that the death penalty is not
intrinsically wrong.
(2) The
Church always taught for 2,000 years that the death penalty is not only not
intrinsically wrong, but that it is generally a good idea and should be used.
I know of
many Catholic defenders of capital punishment who have asserted claim (1),
including myself. But claim (1) is by no
means a “myth.” It is demonstrably true,
as Joseph Bessette and I document in detail in our book By Man Shall His Blood Be Shed: A Catholic
Defense of Capital Punishment.
Indeed, in his
own book on the subject, E. Christian Brugger, the foremost Catholic
theologian who argues against capital punishment – and someone who even claims
that the death penalty is
intrinsically wrong – admits that (1) is true.
In fact, even Fastiggi and Sonna appear to concede it. Fastiggi acknowledges that the Fathers he
cites “don’t necessarily challenge the state’s right to [execute],” but merely
argue against exercising that right. And
Sonna admits that “maybe we can’t dispute that the state has the right,
technically, to do it.”
By contrast,
claim (2) is indeed false, for just the reasons Fastiggi gives. But I cannot think of a single person who endorses
claim (2) in the first place. (Certainly
Joe Bessette and I explicitly acknowledge in our book that some Fathers and
popes held that it was morally better not to resort to the death penalty.) So, when Fastiggi cites what certain of the
Fathers say as evidence against a “myth” he alleges many are peddling, he is
attacking a thesis that no one in fact holds.
It seems otherwise to him and to Sonna only because they ignore the
distinction between (1) and (2).
Misrepresenting John Paul II
Sloppiness
of this kind often leads Fastiggi to misrepresent the views of his opponents
and the nature of their disagreement with him.
It also leads him to misrepresent a pope he appeals to in defense of his
position, namely Pope St. John Paul II. About
seven minutes into the video, Fastiggi suggests that the Church now condemns
not only killing the innocent, but “intentional killing” as such. He says:
The reason why the Church has now developed her teaching to
be opposed to capital punishment is because it involves intentional killing,
and then the question of course of whether or not a murderer loses human
dignity and the right to life. And
really, the turning point of this was St. John Paul II. In Evangelium
Vitae number 9, he says not even a murderer loses his dignity.
After the 50
minute mark, Fastiggi returns to the theme, and says:
I think a leap was made with the understanding that punishing
people by intentionally killing them is an offense against the inviolability of
life. The theoretical question is, does
a serious crime take away the right to life?
And John Paul II answered that in Evangelium
Vitae 9. That was the breakthrough,
that not even a murderer loses his dignity and right to life.
This is
sleight of hand. It is true that Evangelium
Vitae 9 says that “not even a murderer loses his personal
dignity.” But the encyclical nowhere
says that a murderer does not lose his right
to life. Instead, it speaks of “the
absolute inviolability of innocent
human life,” “the inviolable right to life of every innocent human being” and again, of “fundamental human rights,
beginning with the right to life of every innocent
human being”; it says that “as far as the right to life is concerned, every
innocent human being is absolutely
equal to all others”; it teaches that “a law which violates an innocent person's natural right to life
is unjust and, as such, is not valid as a law”; and it calls for “unconditional
respect for the right to life of every innocent
person” (emphasis added). And it
explicitly allows that the execution of those guilty of the gravest offenses is
permissible “in cases of absolute necessity.”
That would not be possible if the murderer never loses his right to
life.
It is true
that Evangelium Vitae also says that
bloodless means are preferable where possible because they are “more in line with human dignity” and “more in conformity to the dignity of the
human person.” But notice that that does
not entail that capital punishment is not
at all in line with human dignity, only that it is less in line with it.
(Compare: To say that Ricky is more talented than Fred does not entail
that Fred is altogether untalented; to say that Ethel is more intelligent than
Lucy does not entail that Lucy is altogether unintelligent; and so on.) So, from the claim that (a) not even a murderer loses his dignity, together
with the claim that (b) the death penalty
is less in line with human dignity than milder punishments, it simply does
not follow that (c) capital punishment is
flatly incompatible with the murderer’s dignity, and neither does it follow
that (d) the murderer does not lose his
right to life. Nor, again, does John
Paul II draw those conclusions.
Perhaps
Fastiggi would say that John Paul II should
have drawn those conclusions, and that in failing to do so he was being
inconsistent. But there are several
problems with such a response. First, it
wouldn’t change the fact that John Paul II did not in fact draw them, and thus did
not in fact say the things Fastiggi attributes to him. Second, for the reasons I have given, the
conclusions do not in fact follow logically from John Paul II’s premises, so
that the pope was not being inconsistent.
Third, if there are two ways of reading a papal document, in one of
which it contains an inconsistency and in the other of which it does not, the
second is to be preferred. Hence, for
that reason alone, we should reject Fastiggi’s reading. Fourth, Fastiggi’s reading would imply that
John Paul II was not only not consistent with himself, but also contradicted
his predecessors – such as Pope Pius XII, who taught:
Even when it is a question of the execution of a man
condemned to death, the State does not dispose of the individual's right to
live. It is reserved rather to the
public authority to deprive the criminal of the benefit of life when already,
by his crime, he has deprived himself of
the right to live. (Address to the First International Congress on the
Histopathology of the Nervous System, 1952, emphasis added)
Certainly,
implicitly to accuse one pope (John Paul II) of inconsistency and another pope (Pius
XII) of grave moral error is a strange way to try to defend a third pope
(Francis)!
In any
event, Joe Bessette and I provide a very detailed analysis of John Paul II’s
teaching at pp. 144-82 of our book. As
we demonstrate there, when one considers the entirety of the evidence (and not
just the usual cherry-picked phrases Catholic opponents of capital punishment
like to quote), it is crystal clear that the pope’s teaching was in no way an
alteration or even development of traditional doctrine, but simply a prudential
judgment about how to apply that doctrine to contemporary circumstances. Like so many of our critics, Fastiggi offers
no response at all to the arguments we give there, but pretends they don’t
exist.
Obfuscating on Pope Francis
Beginning at
about 12 minutes into their discussion, Fastiggi and Sonna argue that Pope
Francis has, in any event, not actually taught that the death penalty is
intrinsically wrong. They focus on the
pope’s 2018 revision to the Catechism, and suggest that it implicitly
acknowledges that capital punishment is permissible in theory, and simply
teaches that it is inadmissible under current circumstances.
This is a
defensible position, as far as it goes.
I have always myself acknowledged that the revision can and should be
read in such a way that it is not teaching that capital punishment is
intrinsically evil. But that is only
part of the story. For one thing, the
problem with the revision is that this is not a natural reading of it. The
revised text characterizes the death penalty as “an attack on the inviolability
and dignity of the person.” On a natural
reading, that seems to imply that capital punishment is intrinsically at odds with human dignity (rather than being at odds
with it only if certain conditions
fail to hold), and thus intrinsically
wrong. Yes, it need not be read that
way, but magisterial statements should be clearly
consistent with traditional teaching, not merely consistent with it on a
strained reading.
For another
thing, other magisterial statements made during Pope Francis’s pontificate are
much harder to reconcile with the traditional teaching. For example, in a
2017 address, the pope asserted that “the death penalty is an
inhumane measure that, regardless of how
it is carried out, abases human dignity.
It is per se contrary to the
Gospel” (emphasis added). The
italicized phrases are most naturally read as claiming that capital punishment
is always and intrinsically wrong.
Some might
reply that this entails only that the death penalty is contrary to the higher
demands of Christian morality, not that it is contrary to natural law. That would be bad enough, because (as I have
shown elsewhere, such as in this
article) the traditional teaching of the Church is that it is not contrary to Christian morality any
more than it is contrary to natural law.
But to make
matters worse, the declaration Dignitas
Infinita, issued by the DDF during Francis’s pontificate,
implies that capital punishment is
contrary even to natural law. For it
asserts that “the death penalty… violates the inalienable dignity of every
person, regardless of the circumstances,” and that this dignity is grounded in
“human nature apart from all cultural change.” The declaration also asserts that human
dignity must be upheld “beyond every circumstance,” “in all circumstances,”
“regardless of the circumstances,” and so on. Here there is no wiggle room for saying that
the document judges capital punishment to be contrary to human dignity only if
certain conditions are not met. For it
flatly asserts that it violates human dignity “regardless of the
circumstances.” Nor is there any wiggle
room for saying that the document nevertheless allows in principle for such a
violation of human dignity under certain circumstances (which would be a
bizarre idea in any case). For it
explicitly says that human dignity “prevails in and beyond every circumstance,
state, or situation the person may ever encounter,” and so on. The logical implication of all this is that
capital punishment is absolutely ruled out as always and intrinsically wrong. And that straightforwardly contradicts
traditional teaching.
Sonna, at
least, appears to acknowledge that the traditional teaching cannot be
reversed. So, if he is going to be
consistent, he will have to admit that these statements issued during Francis’s
pontificate are problematic – that they are poorly formulated at best, and
erroneous at worst (which is possible in non-ex cathedra magisterial statements).
Parallel doctrinal reversals?
Fastiggi is
another story. At around 40 minutes in,
he says: “But hasn’t the Church definitively taught that the death penalty is
allowed? No, it hasn’t.” And earlier, at around 25 minutes in, he says
that “even if the Church has not yet, maybe someday she’ll say it’s
intrinsically immoral, but because it had been accepted for so long we don’t
need to say that right now.”
But Fastiggi
is simply mistaken. When all the
relevant evidence is taken account of, it is manifest that the doctrine that
the death penalty is not intrinsically wrong has been taught by both scripture
and the Church in an irreformable manner.
I set out some of this evidence in a
long Catholic World Report article
from some years back, and Joe Bessette and I do so in greater depth in our
book. Fastiggi says nothing even to
acknowledge, much less answer, these arguments.
He merely begs the question against them.
Fastiggi
also says that even if the Church does not hold that the death penalty is
intrinsically wrong, it doesn’t follow that its teaching against it is merely a
prudential judgment which Catholics need only respectfully consider but not
necessarily follow. For the Church has
the authority to prohibit even certain practices that are not inherently
wrong. Fastiggi gives the example of
cremation, which was for a long time prohibited by the Church but now is
permitted under certain circumstances. He
also cites polygamy and divorce, which were tolerated under the old covenant
but have been forbidden under the new covenant.
Fastiggi is
right about that much, but these facts don’t suffice to show that the Church
can do more than issue a non-binding prudential judgment against use of the
death penalty. The reason is that it is
the state and not the Church which has the responsibility and right under
natural law to do what is necessary to ensure the safety of the community. This is why, after setting out the criteria
for fighting a just war, the Catechism goes on to say that “the evaluation of
these conditions for moral legitimacy belongs to the prudential judgment of
those who have responsibility for the common good” (2309). In other words, the Church can teach that a
war is just only when the cause is just, there is a serious chance of success, no
other options are likely to work, and so on.
But the Church does not have the expertise or authority to determine how
these criteria apply in a particular case.
For example, it does not have the relevant expertise to determine
whether some option other than war would suffice to repel an aggressor in a
particular case, or whether a certain military strategy is likely to
succeed. These are matters of prudential
judgment, and it is the state rather than the Church that has the right and
responsibility to make that judgment.
But the same
applies, mutatis mutandis, to capital
punishment. The revision to the
catechism claims, for example, that modern systems of imprisonment are
sufficient to protect others against the most dangerous offenders. But the Church has no more expertise on that
sort of issue than it does on military strategy. If government officials have good empirical
reason to believe that the death penalty saves lives – for example, if they
have evidence that it has a significant deterrent effect, or that it is needed
to protect prison guards or other prisoners from the most violent offenders –
then they have just as much a right under natural law to utilize capital
punishment as they do to fight a just war.
This sort of
reasoning does not apply to cremation, which is why it is not an interesting
parallel to the case of capital punishment.
The examples of polygamy and divorce also do nothing to help Fastiggi’s
case, and not just because (unlike capital punishment) the state does not need
to keep them open as options in order to do its job of protecting society. There is also the following glaring
disanalogy: The New Testament explicitly forbids
divorce and clearly opposes polygamy too, as has the Church ever since. But the New Testament explicitly allows capital punishment (e.g. in
Romans 13), as has the Church ever since.
Cremation, polygamy, and divorce thus offer no precedent for an absolute
prohibition on capital punishment.
Fastiggi and
Sonna suggest other alleged doctrinal reversals that they think provide a
precedent for a reversal on capital punishment.
But they are all bad analogies that provide no support whatsoever for
such a reversal. For example, Fastiggi
points to the fact that theologians were once free to disagree about the
Immaculate Conception, but later the Church made a dogmatic pronouncement on
the matter so that such legitimate disagreement is no longer possible.
The problem
with this purported analogy should be obvious.
To teach that capital punishment is intrinsically wrong would directly
contradict what the Church had consistently taught for 2,000 years and what she
had always understood scripture to teach.
Proclaiming the dogma of the Immaculate Conception involved nothing
remotely like that. In particular, it in
no way involved the Church contradicting
some doctrine she had previously taught.
Fastiggi
alleges that there is also a parallel between capital punishment and the case
of torture. He contrasts a passing
remark on the subject from Pope Innocent I, which left its use open, with the
more recent teaching of the Church condemning torture. Here too the alleged parallel is
spurious. The Church holds that
scripture cannot teach moral error, and she has for two millennia acknowledged
that scripture repeatedly sanctions capital punishment. But there is no such scriptural sanction for
torture. The Church has also for two
millennia herself consistently and clearly taught that capital punishment can
under certain circumstances be licit, to the point of including this doctrine
in major teaching documents such as the catechisms of Pope St. Pius V and Pope
St. John Paul II. The teaching was also
endorsed by the Fathers (even those who opposed the use of capital punishment
in practice), has been consistently affirmed by the Church’s greatest
theologians (including many Doctors of the Church), and routinely endorsed in
approved manuals of moral theology. None
of this can be said of torture.
Fastiggi and
Sonna also suggest that the development of the Church’s teaching on slavery
provides a precedent for a change on capital punishment. But this alleged parallel too is phony. For one thing, here too Fastiggi and Sonna
muddy the waters by ignoring long-established and crucial distinctions. For the word “slavery” is ambiguous. What most people think of when they hear this
term is chattel slavery, which
involves claiming ownership of another human being in the way one might own an
animal or inanimate object. The Church
does indeed teach that this is intrinsically evil, but she has never taught
otherwise. Indeed, she has condemned
this practice for centuries (as I document in my book All One in
Christ: A Catholic Critique of Racism and Critical Race Theory).
There are,
however, less extreme forms of servitude that the Church has taken to be at
least in theory not unjust. In
particular, there is penal servitude,
which is forced labor in punishment for a crime. The idea here is that if the state can, in
punishment for a sufficiently grave crime, take away an offender’s liberty for
a prolonged period of time (even for life), then it can also require him to
work. And there is indentured servitude, a prolonged period of labor without payment
as a way to repay a debt or in exchange for some benefit. The idea here is that if someone can
legitimately enter a work contract, or have his wages garnished in order to pay
a debt, then by extension he can make himself a servant in order to pay a debt.
The trouble
with these practices is that in concrete circumstances they are fraught with
moral hazard, and were often used to rationalize what amounted to chattel
slavery (such as when captives taken in war were enslaved on the spurious
grounds that they were guilty of the offense of fighting an unjust war, and
thus could be forced into penal servitude).
Hence, moral theologians settled on the view (quite correctly, I would
say) that when all relevant moral considerations are brought to bear, it is
clear that they ought flatly to be banned altogether.
There is
also the consideration that in scripture, slavery is merely tolerated as an
institution that happened to exist, rather than put forward as a positive
good. By contrast, the death penalty is not merely tolerated, but in some cases
is positively sanctioned (not only in the Mosaic law, but in other contexts
such as Genesis 9 and Romans 13).
So, when all
the distinctions are made, the argument that “the Church reversed herself on
slavery, so she can reverse herself on capital punishment” falls apart. There was no such reversal, and thus no
precedent for a reversal on capital punishment.
Magisterial credibility
This brings
us to Fastiggi’s remarks about Genesis 9 and Romans 13, where he repeats claims
that I have already refuted in my previous exchange with him. And once again, he simply ignores rather than
answers the objections I raised there. I
direct the interested reader to that
earlier essay of mine. (In
particular, see the sections titled “Genesis and the death penalty” and “The
Mosaic Law versus the Gospel?”)
Fastiggi
acknowledges that, in the instruction Donum
Veritatis, the Church affirms that Catholics have the right
respectfully to raise questions about deficient magisterial statements and ask
for clarification. He says that this
nevertheless gives Catholics no right to “dissent” from the teaching of the
Church. I agree with him about all
that. But Fastiggi seems to think that
it rules out the sort of respectful criticisms that I and others with the
relevant expertise have raised. It does
not, and I have many times given arguments that show that it does not. These arguments too are ones that Fastiggi
simply ignores rather than tries to answer.
For example,
the criticisms I have raised with respect to the 2018 revision of the Catechism
have nothing to do with “dissenting” from some teaching of the Church. Rather, the whole point is that the teaching
is unclear – that it is far from obvious exactly
what it is that Catholics are being asked to assent to. True, the revision
declares that the death penalty is now “inadmissible.” But the trouble is that the force of this teaching is not
obvious. I
have argued that there are only two ways to read it. On the one hand, it might be read as claiming
that the death penalty is intrinsically
wrong and thus “inadmissible” in an absolute
and unqualified way. The problem is
that this would contradict scripture and tradition, and thus amount to a
doctrinal error (something that can occur in non-ex cathedra statements). Moreover, even Fastiggi and Sonna
acknowledge that this is not the right way to read it.
But when we
take account of all the relevant considerations (both from within the document
and from the larger tradition of the Church), the only other way to read it is
as saying that the death penalty is “inadmissible” unless certain conditions hold (such as that resort to it is necessary
in order to protect society). And if
this is the case, then the teaching amounts to a non-binding prudential
judgment. For the “unless” part is not
something concerning which the Church has any special authority. For example, whether capital punishment has a
significant deterrence effect, and whether modern prison systems really do
afford the means of protecting others from all violent offenders, are empirical
matters of social science, not matters of faith or morals.
For seven
years now, Fastiggi and I have been arguing about this issue, and in all that
time I have never gotten a clear answer from him about what a third possible
interpretation would look like. In any
event, if someone asks me “Do you dissent from the teaching of the revision of
the Catechism?” my answer is “No, I do not dissent from it. I assent to it, and interpret it in the only
way I know of that makes sense – namely, as a non-binding prudential
judgment.” I also say, however, that the
revision is badly formulated and potentially misleading. And I have every right respectfully to raise
such a criticism, by the norms set out in Donum
Veritatis. Fastiggi and others may
continue to yell “Dissent!” but yelling is all they would be doing. I have yet to hear an actual argument showing that my position
amounts to dissent.
I
acknowledge that my criticism of Dignitas
Infinita goes beyond this. Here, I
think we have a document that is not merely ambiguous, but very hard (at best)
to defend from the charge of flatly contradicting scripture and tradition and
thus being erroneous. But if someone has
a plausible way of reconciling it with scripture and tradition, I’m all
ears.
Even if it
is indeed in error, however, this is possible in non-ex cathedra documents.
Indeed, Fastiggi himself is implicitly committed to this thesis. For, again, he holds that the Church could
end up teaching that capital punishment is intrinsically immoral. And if that were correct, it would follow
that for two millennia, the Church got things gravely wrong on matters of basic
moral principle and biblical interpretation.
That is a very radical claim, and indeed far more radical than anything I have said. If I am right, then one pope has gotten
things wrong about capital punishment.
If Fastiggi is right, then every previous
pope who has taught on this topic has been wrong, as have the Fathers and
Doctors of the Church (and indeed scripture itself). Fastiggi likes to paint views like mine as
extreme, but in fact it is his views
that are extreme.
The fact
that he presents them politely and under the guise of obedience to the
magisterium doesn’t change that one whit.
It is the content of the views
that matter, and the content is radically subversive of the credibility of the
Church, because it implies that the Church
may have been gravely in error about a matter of natural law, the demands of
the Gospel, and the proper understanding of scripture for her entire history
until now. And if she could be that
wrong for that long, what else might she be wrong about?
At about one
hour and three minutes into the interview, Fastiggi says, with no sense of
irony: “There has to be trust in the Holy Spirit’s guidance of the
magisterium. And that’s what I find
missing in many of these papal critics.
They don’t trust the Holy Spirit.”
Yet Fastiggi is the one
suggesting that the magisterium may have, for two millennia, consistently erred
about a grave matter of natural law, Christian morality, and scriptural interpretation. Fastiggi
is the one suggesting that the Holy Spirit might have permitted this. But what is more likely – that that is the
case, or that a single pope (Francis) issued a badly formulated catechism
revision and permitted the DDF to slip a doctrinal error into a declaration? I submit that, if the Holy Spirit truly is
guiding the magisterium, the scenario I posit is manifestly more plausible than
the one Fastiggi is positing.
The reality
is that the critics do trust in the Holy
Spirit’s guidance of the magisterium.
They trust that the Holy Spirit would not have allowed the Church to be
that wrong for that long about something that important, so that it must be
those who now contradict the past magisterium who are mistaken. This has always been theoretically possible,
because the Church has always acknowledged that non-definitive exercises of the
magisterium can fall into error. Indeed
this has in fact happened before in the case even of papal teaching, as the famous
examples of popes Honorius I and John XXII illustrate. And Fastiggi’s own position entails it. If, as he insists, it may turn out that two
millennia of past teaching of the magisterium on capital punishment was wrong,
then it follows logically that it is also possible that it is instead Pope
Francis’s statements on the subject that are wrong. And as I have shown elsewhere (here
and here),
the Church has also always affirmed that there can be cases where the faithful
may respectfully criticize the magisterium, even a pope, for teaching contrary
to the tradition.
What Fastiggi
never seems to appreciate is that his approach damages the credibility of the
magisterium by appearing to saddle it with what, in logic, is known as a “No
True Scotsman” fallacy. Suppose I say
“No true Scotsman would be an empiricist,” and you respond “But David Hume was
an empiricist!” And suppose I reply “Well,
then David Hume must not really have
been a true Scotsman,” and that I insist that everybody has for 250 years been
misinterpreting all the evidence that seems obviously to show that he was an
empiricist. Needless to say, this would
not lend me or my thesis any credibility at all, but would do precisely the
opposite. It would reveal me to be
intellectually dishonest and unwilling to look at the evidence objectively.
Now, the
First Vatican Council declared that “the Holy Spirit was promised to the
successors of Peter not so that they might, by his revelation, make known some
new doctrine.” The Second Vatican
Council stated that “the living teaching office of the Church… is not above the
word of God, but serves it, teaching only what has been handed on.” Pope Benedict XVI taught that the pope “must
not proclaim his own ideas… he is bound to the great community of faith of all
times, to the binding interpretations that have developed throughout the
Church's pilgrimage.”
But the
liceity in principle of the death penalty has for two millennia been
consistently taught by the Church, and has for two millennia been understood by
the Church to be the teaching of scripture, which is the word of God. Hence, for a pope to teach that the death
penalty is intrinsically immoral would manifestly be a case of attempting to
“make known some new doctrine.” It would
manifestly be a case of putting himself “above the word of God” instead of
“teaching only what has been handed on.”
It would manifestly be a case of attempting to “proclaim his own ideas”
rather than being “bound to the great community of faith of all times.”
Fastiggi,
however, takes the view that if a pope were to teach such a thing, then the conclusion
we should draw is that the liceity in principle of capital punishment must
after all not really ever have been
the teaching of scripture; that it must not really
be a “new doctrine” but somehow implicit in what scripture and the Church have
always taught; that it must not really
after all have been among “the binding interpretations” to which a pope must
conform himself. And that is like
dogmatically insisting that Hume must not really
have been a true Scotsman after all. It
gives aid and comfort to Protestant and skeptical critics of Catholicism, who
argue that the Church’s claim to continuity with scripture and tradition is a
sham – that at the end of the day, the popes will just teach whatever they like
and then arbitrarily slap the label “traditional” on it.
It may be
that Fastiggi is not sufficiently sensitive to this problem, whereas I have
always emphasized it, in part because of the differences in our academic and
intellectual contexts. Fastiggi is a
theologian teaching at a seminary, the primary job of which is the formation of
priests. And it seems that he writes
pretty much exclusively for Catholic audiences.
I’m a philosopher teaching at a secular college, who often writes on
matters of apologetics. And my writing
is directed as much to the general public as it is to fellow Catholics. When Fastiggi sees Catholics criticizing even
obviously deficient magisterial statements, even in a respectful and well-informed
way, his instinctive reaction appears to be: “It’s unseemly for Catholics to be
doing that, no matter what the pope says!
Just keep quiet, and trust providence to sort it out.” When I see Catholics tying themselves in
logical knots trying to defend obviously deficient magisterial statements, my
instinctive reaction is: “Those are manifestly terrible arguments, you’re
making Catholicism look ridiculous! Just
frankly admit that there’s a problem, and trust providence to sort it out.” What Fastiggi and I agree about is that
providence will sort it out, but we disagree about what form this might take
and what role respectful criticism of deficient magisterial statements can play.
At the end of the day, though, such psychological speculations are not what matter. What matters is what the evidence of scripture, tradition, and the entirety of the magisterial history of the Church (not just the last few years of it) have to say. And as I have argued, that evidence tells decisively against Fastiggi’s position.
It's remarkable how many people, even quite intelligent people, have difficulty recognizing the distinction between the idea that we should work to make society such that we don't need the death penalty, which should in any case be restricted to genuinely protecting the common good and done only with grave caution, rarely, etc., and the idea that the death penalty is morally wrong in and of itself, by its very nature. It's particularly pernicious here, because everyone who rejects the latter gets slapped with an undifferentiated 'pro-death-penalty' label, which is much as if you labeled anyone who believed it is not always wrong to kill someone trying to murder you with a 'pro-killing' label.
ReplyDeleteHi Brandon,
DeleteYes, it's completely unnecessary and counterproductive for anti-capital punishment Catholics constantly to resort to the most extreme characterizations of their opponents and of the death penalty itself. The Fathers who urged the state not to exercise its right to execute managed to avoid doing that. So why can't modern opponents? It reinforces the suspicion that for many of them, the death penalty issue is a stalking horse for other doctrinal changes -- that they want to push for the most extreme sort of change on this issue precisely because they know that would open the door to others.
I fear that underneath the bulk of opposition to the DP is an intense this-worldly view, a secular mind-set that this life is the only life to consider; on that mind-set, it is "impossible" for a human being to lose his right to life, because that's "ALL HE HAS" as the basis for other rights: denying his right to life is tantamount to denying his very personhood. But a Christian view rejects this completely: his immortal soul is a far better ground for his dignity and rights, yet at the same time it expressly allows that death is NOT an "ultimate" indignity to his person, as God can even use his death for good - both for his OWN good and for that of others.
DeleteI believe that most (probably nearly all) of the Church's individuals who are totally opposed to DP and who are not deeply steeped in the Church's history and biblical understanding, are operating in a kind of sympathetic conformity with the mainstream secular humanists whose educated elite have articulated a pseudo-moral-high ground for the anti-DP position. In effect, they are practicing secular humanists even while they believe they are solid Christians. The ones who bother to read snippets of recent Church doctrinal documents - but not earlier ones to achieve perspective - falsely believe that the recent documents constitute explicit affirmation of that pseudo-moral-high ground as articulated by secular humanists, not noticing that even where there is overlap between the Church's expressed conclusions and those of the secularists, it is on a different basis (at least, when it is articulated and not merely hand-waved as if axiomatic and manifest to all).
In practice: we should completely discount the apparent majority view of those "in" the Church on this, as "they know not what they do". I that I were able to say that this majority excludes the bulk of the bishopric.
It's one example of several of how Catholic minds and sensibilities have been corrupted by thoroughly marinating in the essentially liberal and modernist assumptions that pervade our institutions.
DeleteHey Prof
ReplyDeleteThis is such a comprehensive article! It's really good!
On the point of torture, I would actually suggest an article by Dr David Decossimo where he goes into depth as to what separates torture from mere killing. I don't know if you have come across it but I think it would be quite useful to you an article you could cite.
Overall, I think that, if you could add anything to this article, it's probably the fact that the principle of proportionality is concerned with the degree to which the perpetrators will has deviated from the good that it ought to pursue.
This could probably forestall arguments that try to attack the death penalty from the like to like standpoint i.e we wouldn't torture a torturer etc.
I suppose one key point that often is neglected in this debate but deserves attention is the mode of capital punishment. I think you addressed this once briefly in your article Augustine on Capital Punishment. Interested readers can check it out. It's a great article.
I think it would strengthen the case for the death penalty by pointing out why certain methods of punishment we find too gruesome for our times.
For example to show that a punishment like rectal feeding is intrinsically evil is quite difficult. But I think Fr Brian Harrison in article has a good general argument against it where he mentions that torture could attract sexual perverts. I think it can also facilitate tendencies like a lust for violence and domination over other people (This similar to what Augustine thought about gladiator fights)
One could expand on it by pointing out that in our times such things could easily go viral on video camera due to the widespread prevalence of such technology and the general tendency to record things for the sake of views , guards themselves could do it or could be bribed to do and the overall effect on society would be to lend legitimacy a kind of legitimacy to such disordered desires.
Couldn't a similar argument be made against the death penalty? I would say it can be made against certain methods but not all.
For example , to apply a classical natural law analysis, the rectum is responsible for expelling waste from the body, waste which ought not to be discharged anywhere but in its proper place as it is disease prone, foul smelling etc. By nature this is one of those act which requires that the person have control over that faculty such as to avoid stinking up a place. That is why it's one of the first activities that is introduced to us as kids and that old people feel embarassed to ask for assistance as they lose motor control.
Any action rectal feeding or anything else involving the rectum, exercises a kind of control or degree of power over an individual that is extremely unusual, and this would legitimise such kind of lust for control. I mentioned how things go viral.
In contrast something like choking (hanging) or lethal injection represents a degree of control that is mundane, it could of course be something that triggers people's lust for violence but at the same time something like a choke hold is a routine part of formal martial arts and self defence or subduing a criminal, it can be classified as something that a person ought to know precisely for the purposes of self defence.It's something that already is very common in society and thus death by hanging or lethal injection wouldn't "by itself" involve facilitating the promotion of disordered tendencies. It's an act that is already mainstream Someone with a disordered attraction to it could just as easily come across it in other places. In contrast , the vitalization of a punishment like rectal feeding is what would make a fringe act mainstream and thus ought to be prohibited.
Anyways I hope that this slightly long comment could be of use to you Prof. Thanks for all your work. I am grateful.
Thanks, Norm. The question of which methods are appropriate is a good one and more needs to be said about it. Suan raises the point at the end of the interview that there is something wrong with people taking a celebratory tone toward execution, and I agree with him about that. I also think it should not be drawn out or gruesome and that it should be solemn, with an emphasis on urging the offender to repent and to offer his punishment up as a penance, praying for him, and so forth. I'll write on this in more depth at some point.
DeleteWould gladly look forward to it Prof. You have from time to time briefly addressed it, Your article and Rehabilitation was also an article I found to be quite interesting where I think you were responding to Brugger. Obviously your more recent article on corporal punishment is relevant.
DeleteYes repentance is important. And obviously not taking a celebratory tone. And emphasizing prison ministry of priests etc.
Do you think my analysis above based on degree of control exerted and societal implications it could entail is a good way of drawing some distinctions between actions to rule out certain kinds of punishments as I did above?
If it's not too much trouble.
I would not object to a state declaring a state-wide day of prayer and penitence on a day of execution, to counteract any sense of celebration of the killing.
Delete“Do you dissent from the teaching of the revision of the Catechism?” my answer is “No, I do not dissent from it. I assent to it, and interpret it in the only way I know of that makes sense – namely, as a non-binding prudential judgment.” I also say, however, that the revision is badly formulated and potentially misleading.
ReplyDeleteThe problem here is that the 'potentially' is really misleading. The revision is actually 'misleading' -- except that it was almost certainly intended to be 'misleading,' so calling it misleading in fact looks to be disingenuous trading on ambiguity. If you do not assent to the natural reading, if you admit that it is badly formulated and misleading, then it seems you are withholding assent, which is indeed a form of dissent. Qualified dissent, but still real dissent. And good for you! You should dissent from false teachings of false teachers.
Well, "dissent" is ambiguous. On the everyday usage of the word, any disagreement counts as a kind of dissent. But the word has a narrower, technical meaning in Catholic contexts that has to do with refusing to assent to some teaching that the Church puts forward as binding on Catholics (which includes infallible teachings but other things too). But Donum Veritatis explicitly says that respectfully raising questions about deficient magisterial statements does not count as "dissent" in this sense.
DeleteIt seems obvious that it is not possible to either assent or dissent unqualifiedly from an inherently unclear teaching. You can say, "I assent because the pope taught it, but I'm not really sure what he is teaching," but that's not 'real' assent, and not worth much (I dare say) in the eyes of God or man. Mutatis mutandis for dissent.
DeleteThat said, I wonder if you (can/should) really assent to JPII's teaching that the death penalty is to be 'absolutely' avoided except in case of 'absolute necessity' (i.e., prudentially considered!), because it is inherently "more in line with human dignity" to use bloodless means of punishment, regardless of the crime being punished. Is that position too not contrary to the teaching of scripture (esp. Rom 13:4) and the sound Catholic theological tradition?? Is JPII not implying that Paul is wrong to say that the state is God's minister to execute vengeance on evildoers, when he wants to limit the role of the state to protecting the innocent?
And so also, I agree we shouldn't crassly 'celebrate' when an evildoer is executed; but we should take a sober satisfaction in the upholding of justice and rightly ordered obedience to the divine will. And we should lament the deeds of those who have used their magisterial office to obscure and subvert the divinely established moral order.
I believe it is not inconsistent with Donum Veritatits to argue that JPII made an editorial mistake in putting his prudential judgment into a Catechism. It's not the place. Fine for putting it into the encyclical (such as Evangelium Vitae), but a Catechism is for timeless truths that are well settled not only as doctrine but also as phrasing. Similarly, he changed the phrasing for how to apply the "safety" basis for DP 3 times in 5 years: the 1992 Catechism, EV, and the 1997 Catechism all employ different phrasing having importantly different senses. His own thought on the issue was changing, and he shouldn't have saddled a Catechism with that process.
DeleteMore significantly is his use of the following:
Assuming that the guilty party's identity and responsibility have been fully determined, the traditional teaching of the Church does not exclude recourse to the death penalty, if this is the only possible way of effectively defending human lives against the unjust aggressor.
The problem is more apparent if you separate it into 2 propositions instead of 1:
A: The traditional teaching of the Church allows recourse to the death penalty.
B: Traditional teaching of the Church allows recourse to the death penalty if and only if this is the only possible way of effectively defending human lives against the unjust aggressor.
(In other articles, Professor Fastiggi argued for this inserted sense using "only if" as the proper interpretation of the Latin, and I admit his claim is plausible, though I cannot find the Latin text to review it.)
Set aside the theological issue for the moment: both A and B make historical claims. The historical accuracy of A is unquestionable. The historical accuracy of B is not. Indeed, it is hard to justify it AT ALL in history, much less establish it as reliable and certain. The best that can be said of B (if this is indeed the best reading of the text) is that it is a backwards reading of JPII's theological thesis (for the "only if" part) into a less-than-perfectly-definitive prior Church analysis of why and when DP is allowable. One could not even propose that JPII's theological thesis (ignoring its historical preface) was the preferred or leading contender for the state of the question. If it was articulated at all (and I have had trouble finding that, but maybe that's me), it was a minority opinion at best, and more likely it was a highly dubious minority opinion, as it opposes a wealth of better-articulated positions that speak to the common good as a whole.
I am not a theologian, and I am not as confident of this as I would like, but I don't think JPII's phrasing can be taken as putting a magisterial approval on the HISTORICAL aspect of the claim, i.e. "the magisterium hereby approves the aforesaid minority and dubious thesis and hereby MAKES it the historically affirmed position". I think the historicity stands or falls on the evidence, not on magisterial shielding. And it's not defensible historically.
If I am right about that, then the passage should be interpreted in the following way: A is true, and the thesis in B (about "only if") is hereby proposed to be the only basis on which A is true. The "traditional teaching" claim ONLY applies to A.
This would leave us free to DEBATE the "only if" part of B on its own terms, i.e. allow us to hash it out fair and square without deference to a presumption it is true because it was the traditional teaching.
I think some people would like to claim that B is really to be understood as saying merely that "IF DP is ever allowed, it is only ever allowed for safety of persons", (a conditional claim) and then add in Francis to be saying "but in fact, even safety of persons cannot EVER justify DP." I think this would represent creeping distortion of "traditional teaching," one mistake piled on top of another.
I concur with David that careful thinkers should be cautious on accepting the proposition that DP is necessarily "less in line with human dignity". I think that once you get that punishment itself is "more in line with human dignity" as it affirms the moral value - and responsibility - of the criminal, you can't easily get DP somehow departs from that model. The proportionality aspect that is built into moral worth (and grounds rewards as well as punishments) leads inexorably to DP as fitting to certain crimes and criminals, and that JUST IS "more in keeping" with the dignity of rational beings with moral freedom. One might argue that "well, yes, the criminal deserves death, but it is not fitting for civil society be the instrument of that death, it belongs to God. But this runs square up against Genesis 9:6 where God assigns it explicitly to humans, and the passage as a whole seems to be explaining natural law, (referring to man's nature in the beginning).
DeleteI think the requirement to lean against using DP except when "necessary" should be related to the whole good which the civil government ought to promote: there are common goods (justice, and virtue), public goods (a general sense of safety), and personal goods (freedom from this prisoner's future depredations, AND this prisoner's own future physical life) in the balance: a presumption that the last item trumps ALL OTHER considerations so completely as to make them irrelevant has...virtually nothing to recommend it philosophically.
As I've long argued, the dignity rhetoric is vague and unnecessary at best and at worst a Trojan horse for ideas that can't be reconciled with natural law and tradition. It should never have become so central. My point in the article is that even if one grants it, JP2 did not actually use it in a way that has the implications that Fastiggi (and others, such as Brugger) think it has.
DeleteRe the “practical” rationale that modern prison systems are sufficient to prevent/deter further criminal acts by the murderer…. This should not to be easily conceded. Powerful gangster/organized criminals continue issuing orders, including death warrants, from their prisons.
ReplyDeleteYes indeed. That is one of several ways in which the suggestion that modern prisons suffice to protect people just isn't true. Joe Bessette and I discuss this in our book, and in the eight years since it appeared, I think not a single critic has responded to that point (if memory serves). Just crickets. It shows how unserious most of them are.
DeleteI'm not an opponent of the death penalty (not in principle, at least). I'm not a Catholic or a believer in natural law either, so I'm not sure whether any comment I make on this article, which is directly about the Catholic perspective, would be relevant. But I think the problems of prison violence and recidivism are indeed some of the strongest arguments for maintaining the death penalty. However, aren't there places (such as some European countries) that don't have the death penalty and have very low rates of prison violence and recidivism (much lower than, say, the U.S.)? Mind you, I'm not sure how much of that is really because of factors such as better prison conditions versus how much other factors that governments may not be able to do much about, such as population size or culture, are causing it. I think it's something that's worth discussing in this debate, as I have seen it brought up elsewhere.
DeleteThis was wonderful Ed. Very clearly written!
ReplyDeleteEd: “I acknowledge that my criticism of 'Dignitas Infinita' goes beyond this. Here, I think we have a document that is not merely ambiguous, but very hard (at best) to defend from the charge of flatly contradicting scripture and tradition and thus being erroneous. But if someone has a plausible way of reconciling it with scripture and tradition, I’m all ears.”
ReplyDeleteA couple of points about the relevant sentence in 'Dignitas Infinita' 34 that make an interpretation consistent with the previous magisterium more defensible:
First, repeating the text itself: ‘Here, one should also mention the death penalty, for this also violates the inalienable dignity of every person, regardless of the circumstances.’
The official text, as printed in 'Acta Apostolicae Sedis' (An. et vol. CXVI, N. 5, 3 May 2024, p. 608), is the Italian:
‘Bisognerà pure qui menzionare il tema della pena di morte: anche quest’ultima, infatti, viola la dignità inalienabile di ogni persona umana al di là di ogni circostanza.’
1. The English version is accurate enough – except that it adds a comma after ‘person’, which is not in the original Italian after ‘persona umana’ (and the English also leaves out ‘human’ as a translation of ‘umana’, which is not relevant here).
In a natural reading, adding the comma increases the plausibility of the interpretation that the phrase ‘regardless of the circumstances’ relates directly to the verb ‘violates’. This makes the sentence more amenable to the interpretation that the death penalty is being indicated as intrinsically evil, since it would violate human dignity regardless of circumstances.
However, omitting the comma (which is the accurate thing to do) increases the plausibility of the interpretation that the phrase ‘regardless of the circumstances’ relates directly either to ‘inalienable dignity’ or ‘every person’ - acting in either case as a redoubling of the affirmation of inalienability.
The meaning would be, on this interpretation: every person regardless of circumstances has this dignity intrinsically, and the death penalty violates that. (Thus it is neither affirmed nor denied that the death penalty violates this inalienable dignity intrinsically, regardless of circumstances: the weaker interpretation is left open that 'for practical purposes, in our world’s current social circumstances', it virtually always violates dignity.)
2. The sentence has a footnote reference (56) to the revised paragraph of the Catechism (n. 2267), and to the CDF’s 'Letter to Bishops Regarding the New Revision of Number 2267 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church on the Death Penalty' nn. 7-8.
ReplyDeleteIf there is ambiguity (as there is, especially with the comma omitted), we need to interpret the sentence in view of the footnote. And the footnote indicates that the CDF understands and intends its sentence in 'Dignitas Infinita' to be reiterating, or at least significantly supported by, the texts referred to.
As Ed has said, the revised Catechism paragraph is itself at least open to an interpretation consistent with the previous magisterium.
Also, the 'Letter to Bishops' explicitly affirms that the doctrine of the Catechism is ‘in continuity with the preceding Magisterium’ (7) and ‘is not in contradiction with the prior teachings of the Magisterium’ (8).
Granting for the sake of argument that this absence of contradiction cannot be created by mere fiat if there does appear to be a fairly evident contradiction, the text of the 'Letter' does at least establish that Pope Francis and the CDF did not intend to be interpreted as contradicting the past magisterium. So if there is a plausible interpretation of the relevant texts that harmonizes with this claim of non-contradiction, then that is the interpretation we must take.
Finally, the 'Letter to Bishops' (7) makes it the dignity of the person ‘that is not lost’ regardless of circumstances, ‘even after having committed the most serious crimes’ - so the fact that 'Dignitas Infinita' makes reference to this passage, reaffirms the interpretation of 'Dignitas Infinita' that it intends ‘regardless of circumstances’ to relate directly to ‘the inalienable dignity of every person’, not to the verb ‘violates’.
In short: if the revised Catechism is open to (or indeed, requires) an interpretation consistent with the previous magisterium, then likewise for 'Dignitas Infinita'.
The issue runs deeper than simply the application of the death penalty. Abolitionists argue for a schizophrenic juridical system, in essence utilitarian, in which the application of justice is a tertiary end, if it is an end at all. This, if carried to its logical conclusion would collapse the justice system itself. It undermines the entire logic behind it, which always must be primarily justice.
ReplyDeleteYou argue, with characteristic precision, that the Magisterium’s recent language on the death penalty represents not a development but a departure, a contradiction of two millennia of consistent teaching. You frame this as a matter of doctrinal fidelity, a defence of what the Church has always taught against innovations that threaten her credibility. Yet what appears to you as reversal may in fact be a transformation in the metaphysical horizon within which the same truth is now perceived. The Church’s moral imagination has not abandoned its foundations; it has deepened them.
ReplyDeleteFor centuries, Christian reflection unfolded within a linear conception of time: birth, earthly existence, death, and an “afterlife” extending along that same continuum. Within that view, death marked the transition from the temporal to the eternal, and to kill, even justly, was simply to move that moment forward. The logos of the person, their eternal vocation, remained intact; only the timing changed. Thus, capital punishment could be accepted as legitimate, since it seemed only to adjust the chronology, not the essence, of a human life.
But as the Church’s metaphysical imagination has matured, drawing especially on St Maximus the Confessor’s vision of creation as an ascent into the Logos, a different understanding has emerged. This maturation, evident throughout twentieth-century ressourcement theology, marks what Henri de Lubac called “the recovery of the mystery of participation,” by which “the supernatural is no longer conceived as a second story built upon nature, but as the interior transformation of all being by grace” (Surnaturel, 1946, p. 470). Creation is no longer understood as a neutral stage upon which God occasionally acts, but as a dynamic movement already being drawn into Him.
Pope Benedict XVI articulated this shift with striking clarity: “eternity is not an unending succession of days in the calendar, but something more like the supreme moment of satisfaction, in which totality embraces us and we embrace totality” (Spe Salvi §12). Likewise, he taught that “time itself becomes a dimension of God’s self-communication” (Eschatology: Death and Eternal Life, 1988, p. 115). The temporal, therefore, is not a flat line leading to eternity, but a field already irradiated by it. Death, in this light, is not merely a step along a horizontal continuum; it is the terminus of the earthly form of life that can be transposed vertically into the eternal.
(cont.)
Every moment of earthly existence thus possesses ontological weight: it is not simply one instant among others, but a participation in the eternal form toward which it is destined. As Hans Urs von Balthasar writes, “Each finite moment bears within itself the whole drama of the eternal decision” (Theo-Drama V, 1998, p. 83). Nicolas Loudovikos, interpreting Maximus for our age, calls this the “verticalisation of temporality,” the transformation of linear time into “a Eucharistic ascent of all being into its eschatological fulfilment in the Logos” (Analogical Identities, 2019, p. 214). From this horizon, to end a life prematurely, even under the pretext of justice, is not merely to alter its duration but to deform the total offering of that life as it is being drawn into God.
DeleteSeen thus, the Church’s renewed opposition to the death penalty is not a denial of her past but a deepening of it. You are right that the Church cannot contradict herself, but she can grow in her apprehension of what her truths entail. Killing in self-defence or in a just war remains morally licit because it preserves the possibility of life and order. Yet when the state executes one who no longer poses a direct threat, it no longer acts as guardian of life but as agent of its interruption. The metaphysical horizon has shifted from time measured along a line to time gathered up into eternity.
This same understanding clarifies why euthanasia and abortion are wrong, not only because they violate a commandment, but because they disfigure the logos of a human life meant to be offered to God in its fullness. The final days or years of a suffering person are not meaningless intervals before heaven; they are part of the temporal pattern that God intends to gather into eternity. Likewise, to destroy an unborn or newly baptized child is not to hasten its beatitude, but to sever the form of life by which God intended to glorify Himself through that person’s unfolding.
If you read the Church’s language on dignity through this metaphysical lens, you may see that her deepening resistance to the death penalty arises from the same seamless vision that grounds her opposition to euthanasia and abortion. What is at stake in each case is the eternal significance of temporal being. As Joseph Ratzinger observed, eternity is not endless duration but “the interpenetration of time by divine presence.”
To trust the Magisterium, then, is not to imagine that it arbitrarily changes course, but to believe that the Spirit continues to draw the Church into the fullness of truth. What you regard as a change of judgment may in fact be the unveiling of the same truth within a transfigured horizon: that every life, in every moment of its earthly duration, is already a participation in the eternal, and that to preserve that life is to cooperate in the world’s ascent into God.
I welcome the idea that the popes (and others) want to push a development of doctrine on this (and other) issues. I object to the idea that it is "development" to simply throw out a new idea not obviously in line with the past teaching and claim "you get from here to there by development". No: development is to provide the pathway by which you get from here to there.
DeleteAnd I decline to follow along with re-imagining life meaning to what you suggest representing that pathway that tells us the DP is inherently improper, from the past teaching.
“a Eucharistic ascent of all being into its eschatological fulfillment in the Logos” (Analogical Identities, 2019, p. 214). From this horizon, to end a life prematurely, even under the pretext of justice, is not merely to alter its duration but to deform the total offering of that life as it is being drawn into God.
It doesn't do the job: God can (and, apparently, WILL) accomplish that "Eucharistic fulfillment of all being" regardless of whether we end it a bit earlier or not. Or, take a baby who dies because some tired pharmacist filled out a prescription wrong: why isn't it the case that baby's life being ended prematurely "deform the total offering of that life as it is being drawn into God"? Or a 4 year old who dies in an accident? No: God's infinite power can take even a criminal's well-deserved death and make it conform to His Plan just fine, and our actions will not defeat that Plan. And justice tells us that the death of the murderer at his execution is NOT "premature" at all, but exactly the time that God Himself allotted, "by which God intended to glorify Himself through that person’s unfolding."
There appears to be a fundamental disconnect between what you imagine to be the eschatological fulfillment and the meaning of acts in this life: in order for acts in this life to "have meaning", they have to have some effect as to the ultimate form of the fulfillment as to its particulars in us at that final denouement. If God WILL accomplish his end - the same end regardless of whether we kill this murderer or not - then his death doesn't "mean anything" (and neither does his life). But at the same time, if that ultimate end doesn't reflect our acts of justice differently than if we were instead to act unjustly, then that again shows our actions - and our lives in their particularities - are meaningless.
God will take our acts of justice and perhaps magnify them incomprehensibly in His glorious culmination. But He cannot at one and the same time do that with our acts of justice, AND say that some acts of justice are unjust because they changed how He "was going to" unfold that person's life if we hadn't done those acts of justice. The explanation doesn't explain, and the "development" doesn't develop. All we're offered is "Now we understand better and ...(energetic hand-waving..."inadmissible".
And it's inconsistent to say that
Killing in self-defence or in a just war remains morally licit because it preserves the possibility of life and order. Yet when the state executes one who no longer poses a direct threat, it no longer acts as guardian of life but as agent of its interruption.
and also to say that the Church (in Francis's new 2267) has said DP is wrong in all cases. He has RULED OUT the DP where needed to defend from that criminal's future attacks, it's "inadmissible" as a violation of dignity.
Pope Leo opposes the application of the death penalty and so did the three popes who preceded him. Were they all wrong? I will accept their judgment over that of the moderator of this blog.
ReplyDeleteVery, very interesting discussion right here!
ReplyDeleteOne thing that the guys who tell us that the death penalty is "unjust," unreflective (or even deliberately) do is eschew the victim from the picture and keep the full focus on the perpetrator (I'm not saying the gentleman in the video did that, I'm just saying that people who held this position are very often soft-hearted towards the criminal). But, I will not focus exclusively on this theological matter -- even though I think it is a moral defect and a grave sin to be merciful towards the criminal and cruelly disregard the victim.
The point I want to focus on is that the so-called "penalists" or "humanist penalists" often overlook (again, either irreflectively or deliberately). To be sure, the death penalty IS MOST DEFINITELY NOT a matter of mere crime prevention, "instrumentalizing the man," or "negative prevention by fear," as they usually say -- these are just secondary effects. The truth is that the death penalty is to serve justice, firstly towards the victim and their family or even the society at large -- and, sometimes, it's the only way to serve justice, given the gravity of the crime.
It doesn't take one far to see how unjust it is to keep a convicted murderer alive. Take Brazil as an example. A man associated with criminal factions or crime syndicates goes on to murder the family of the whistleblower who, courageously, denounced the criminal schemes. The murderer will be jailed, sustained by taxpayers' money, and will not even serve two decades in jail (since here in Brazil, you can't serve more than 30 years in prison, and, most of the time, these sentences are not fully dutied because the criminal is "entitled" to a progression of regime that he could serve in probation, out of the jail).
The little example I gave above, which is unfortunately part of reality, leaves us with the following question: what kind of 'justice' do we get in the mind of society, the victim's family, and even in the mind of the perpetrator himself, if a murderer could simply "walk" and live on his life after committing one of the gravest sins of all time? By permitting even the minimal injustice of leaving a murderer alive, the criminal system only raises the feeling of injustice and civil unrest, and, undeniably, the victim, who is the most crucial part of the criminal picture, remains unserved by justice.
I think the history of the Church’s doctrinal treatment of DP, from Innocent I’s statement of the issue in 405 until 2018, has been clear and incontrovertibly in favor of DP being morally licit under the natural law. The history before that may be more ambiguous. Here is, I think, a fair and balanced description:
ReplyDelete1. The apostles accepted DP: (a) They concretely indicated approval, (St. Paul, in Romans 13:1-4; (b) they clearly called it forth (St. Peter in Acts 5:1-10), (c) they recorded explicit affirmation of it (Luke 23:41 (the Good Thief) ), and (d) otherwise simply allowed its existence without opposition or demurral (the Gospels as a whole). Everything they wrote that touches on the use of the DP at least implicitly accepts it, and nothing they wrote disapproves of it as a general matter.
2. After the apostles, for much of the next 250 years (before Constantine), the early Fathers were mixed: of the ones who spoke on it (not all by any means), most of them clearly disapproved of its practice in some references. Some of them seemed to give as reasons a position that sounds general in its disapproval, and yet in other references they seemed to accept it, thus they muddled their own opposition. Origen and Tertullian, two of the most promient early teachers, expostulated against it (and opponents of DP often pull out quotes from these two), but in other places they admitted its liceity. Of the ones that wrote against DP and there appears to be no passages from them that also accepted it, generally their disapproval of it is ambiguous, in that it is less than clear whether their opposition was against it in principle and for all cases, or in practice given the mores of the times and its particulars.
3. In the 4th century, after Constantine, most of the Fathers that spoke on it clearly supported its liceity in principle even if they broadly opposed its regular and easy practice, and often urged against using it.
Under the principles of development of doctrine, the explicit determination of Innocent I in 405 interprets this past ambiguity of the record, in favor of the LICEITY of the DP under both the natural law and under the Gospels, and pushed the Church to model the sometime opposition of earlier Fathers into an antipathy based on practices and particulars, not based on a per se violation of proper dignity. The next 1590 years (to JPII’s Catechism) represent an unbroken affirmation of Innocent’s determinative conclusion and further refinement of the thinking behind which the moral liceity of DP is understood not to be a per se violation of the proper dignity of a criminal lawfully found to be guilty of grave crime.
Moral, philosophical, and theological necessity dictates that development of doctrine ONLY GOES IN ONE DIRECTION. Even if the record of the early Fathers appears at times to allow a conclusion that maybe the DP is per se immoral, the clear determination of Innocent on the issue and the development of doctrine that actually occurred over 1660 years after Constantine does not permit us to allow that “appears at times” to represent any foundation for NOW arguing that DP is illicit. The Church has spoken on that ambiguity and settled it. You can’t keep using it in later times, when the development process laid it to rest – that’s what the one-way direction implies. There had been NO ambiguity on the issue for 1590 years, including on how to read the ambiguity of the earlier years.
Consequently, while it was true for a period that the record was ambiguous, after the Church addressed that ambiguity, even that period is no longer ambiguous, and it is more correct to say that there is a 2000-year record wherein the Church firmly teaches the liceity of the DP.
Great post --- for what it is worth, Dr. Feser, as a lay Catholic who has spent very considerable time investigating the faith intellectually, and who has had significant doubts in the past due in part to weak teachers unskilled in apologetics, I think that the sort of attitude had by Fastiggi probably not infrequently contributes to doubts about Catholicism among intellectually-inclined, honest Catholics and non-Catholic seekers alike: Fastiggi is, I take it, a reputable theologian at a Catholic college, but he went on air and pulled what looked (to me) like sophistry: he strawmanned death-penalty advocates as dissenters who like revenge, does not answer Suan's questions plainly (it felt like he really wanted to say the death penalty is intrinsically immoral, and maybe is, but he didn't exactly say it --- felt kinda moat-and-bailey), and adopted what frankly felt like a somewhat manipulative attitude/tone ('you trust the Holy Spirit, don't you? then stop 'dissenting' '). This sort of thing leads at least some --- who knows how many? --- to question the honesty of the Church's intellectual institutions, including people like myself who want to trust them. I don't know if I'm being too harsh on Fastiggi, but people who represent Catholic intellectual life in public should hold themselves to higher standards and avoid cheap debate tactics. [N.B. I consider myself pretty non-partisan regarding the death penalty debate --- I accept whatever the Church teaches, and don't have an agenda beyond consistency with magisterial tradition and natural law.]
ReplyDeleteIt seems to me that some people who defend Francis's revision and argue against the DP, e.g. Fasttiggi, may be motivated by a fear that the Pope will declare "ex cathedra" that the DP is intrinsically wrong. Thus, in defending the possibility that the DP is intrinsically wrong, they are in some sense laying the groundwork for a defense of the Church should she make such a declaration.
ReplyDeleteI am curious Professor Feser, how you would respond to that worry? I imagine you think it is unlikely (maybe even impossible). But if it did happen, would this mean we should be sedevecantists? How should a Catholic respond?