But such a
reaction would reflect a misunderstanding of the book’s title. “Philosophical experience,” as Gilson uses
the phrase, has nothing to do with some way of life or psychological profile that
philosophers share in common. He’s not
concerned with “what it’s like to be a philosopher,” as Thomas Nagel might say. A clue to what he does mean is provided by the titles he gives the book’s first three
parts, viz. “The Medieval Experiment,” “The Cartesian Experiment,” and “The
Modern Experiment.” The “experience” referred
to in Gilson’s title is analogous to the experience on which empirical science
rests. It has to do with a kind of experimentation to which certain
philosophical ideas have, in a way, been put.
What way is
that? Gilson holds that “the history of philosophy
is to the philosopher what his laboratory is to the scientist” (p. 95). The theories of empirical science entail
predictions which can be tested by observation.
By contrast, metaphysical theories, which concern matters that transcend
what can be observed, cannot be tested that way. All the same, such theories also have their
entailments, and if a metaphysical theory leads to conclusions that are
incoherent or otherwise known to be false, then we have grounds for rejecting
it. Now, given the limitations of the
individual human intellect, not all the implications of a metaphysical theory
are ever worked out or understood by the individual thinker who came up with
it. We need to look to what his
successors had to say in developing further the thinker’s premises, taking them
in new directions, criticizing them, and so on.
Hence it is to the history of philosophy, rather than to the laboratory,
that we must look in order to test metaphysical theories. The “experiments” to which such a theory is put
are, essentially, embodied in the historical record of what happened as the
theory was developed and criticized in this way.
What about
the “unity” referred to by Gilson in his title?
Gilson is speaking here of the way that, as he argues, a number of
philosophical theories from the Middle Ages to the present have made a similar
type of opening move and been led thereby into the same problematic
outcome. The opening move in question is
essentially that of trying to transform metaphysical questions into questions
of some other type. The problematic
outcome is skepticism about metaphysics.
But this skepticism always turns out to be intellectually
unsatisfactory, so that it is always followed by a renewed attempt at
metaphysics – but often one that makes a new opening move of the same general
type, so that the cycle begins again. The
lesson this series of experiments teaches us is that it is a mistake to make an
opening move of the type in question.
Examples of
this sort of move that are discussed by Gilson include the attempt to reduce
metaphysical questions to questions of logic, which Gilson associates with
Peter Abelard. There is also the attempt
to resolve metaphysical questions by way of theology, which Gilson associates
with thinkers like Bonaventure. Ockham,
Gilson argues, essentially tries to resolve metaphysical questions by appeal to
human psychology. Descartes does so by
modeling all knowledge on mathematics.
Kant, Gilson says, modeled it on Newtonian physics, and Comte on sociology. Such views (which Gilson calls logicism, theologism, psychologism,
mathematicism, physicism, and sociologism,
respectively) essentially try to turn metaphysics into something else. They do so by taking one part of reality (such as mathematical truth, or physical reality,
or the human mind) and modeling the whole
of reality on it.
But
metaphysics by its nature is concerned precisely with the whole – with being qua being – so that attempts to make
it about a part of the whole, thereby distorting it, will inevitably fail. Critics of metaphysics conclude from this
series of failures that there is something wrong with metaphysics itself, but
this is a non sequitur. For the failures
reflect the distortion of metaphysics rather than anything in the nature of metaphysics
itself. And that metaphysical inquiry
keeps reviving even in the wake of these failures reflects the fact that there
are real questions that it alone can address – questions that go deeper than
those addressed by the other branches of human knowledge that too many
metaphysicians have mistakenly tried to model metaphysics on.
This is the
context in which Gilson makes his famous remark that “philosophy always buries
its undertakers” (p. 246). This, he
suggests, is a “law” established by the philosophical “experiments” he has
described in the book (in a way analogous to the manner in which physical laws
are established by physical experiment).
And there are further laws that are so established, such as the law that
“by his very nature, man is a metaphysical animal” (p. 248) and the law that “as
metaphysics aims at transcending all particular knowledge, no particular
science is competent either to solve metaphysical problems, or to judge their
metaphysical solutions” (p. 249). He
takes “philosophical experience” thereby to have vindicated the approach of
thinkers like Aristotle and Aquinas (though he emphasizes that this does not
entail that they have given us the last word).
Gilson’s
account suggests the following analogy (mine, not his). Heresy, in the strict theological sense,
involves plucking some element of Christian doctrine out from its larger
dogmatic context and thereby distorting it.
(The word “heresy” comes from the Greek hairesis, which connotes “taking” or “choice.”) For example, monophysitism so emphasizes
Christ’s divinity that it destroys his humanity, thereby distorting the thesis
that Jesus is God. Modalism so
emphasizes divine unity that it destroys the distinctness of the three divine
Persons, thereby distorting the doctrine of the Trinity. And so on.
The metaphysical errors Gilson describes are analogous to this, insofar
as they involve “taking” or “choosing” some part of reality (mathematics,
physics, mind, or whatever) and erroneously modeling the whole on it, thereby
distorting both the whole and the part.
We can extend the analogy further. Pope St. Pius X, in Pascendi Dominici Gregis, famously characterized modernism as “the synthesis of all heresies.” Philosophy since the time of Ockham has had an analogous character, so that it is no accident that most (though, admittedly, not all) of what Gilson recounts in The Unity of Philosophical Experience occurred after his time, and during the post-medieval period especially. Modern philosophy can therefore be characterized as a kind of “synthesis of all metaphysical errors.” It has recapitulated errors seen previously in the history of philosophy (such as in the Pre-Socratic period) but ramified and exacerbated them, and in a relatively short historical period. And because the moral and political errors characteristic of the modern world have followed from these metaphysical errors, Gilson’s book is a key text for understanding not just modern philosophy, but modernity in general.
"But its bulk is devoted to detailed accounts of the ideas of thinkers Gilson regards as having gotten things badly wrong, such as Abelard, Ockham, Descartes, Malebranche, Kant, and Comte." He goes into much greater detail in his "History of Modern Philosophy."
ReplyDeleteAs a scientist, I wish that we had a similar "Journal of Negative Results".
ReplyDeleteParapsych scientists are among the best at reporting negative results, including proponents!
DeleteCould we say that analytic philosophy attempts to do the same thing with linguistics?
ReplyDeletePeter Geach would have agreed with you. In his "A philosophical autobiography", he writes:
Delete"In my youth what has been called the linguistic turn was all the fashion ... the label is meant for attempts to solve or dissolve philosophical problems by shifting from talk about non-linguistic entities to talk about language.
The Tractatus made me aware that often this technique will not work, and why it will not; very often the problem supposedly dissolved by this shift only reappears at the level of language - not surprisingly, since language is just one part of the world."
Just bought this on the basis of the recommendation above. It's great. Not for beginners, but fine if you have a solid grasp of the basics. The wry French humour is glorious and appears on almost every page without getting in the way of the narrative -- quite the opposite. Strongly recommended.
Deletemetaphysical theories, which concern matters that transcend what can be observed, cannot be tested [by observation].... if a metaphysical theory leads to conclusions that are incoherent or otherwise known to be false,
ReplyDeleteThis is the burning question I have for metaphysicians: How do you evaluate the quality of your work? How do you test your own theories, beyond empirical observation and logic?
With regard to "incoherent" and "false", they seem to mean different things to different people. Especially in discussions of philosophy and theology, I've frequently heard people say some idea is "incoherent", but the same idea seems coherent to me. Come to think of it, what people mean by "incoherent" is actually inconsistent with their own presuppositions, which are different from mine. So as long as we disagree on the underlying presuppositions, and as long as these presuppositions cannot be falsified using criteria acceptable by both sides, our metaphysical discussion is not going to be productive.
Natural science faces similar issues. How do you know if a theory has been falsified or not? People will disagree on the interoperation of certain data, what counts as a datum, they can modify theories to remain untouched, etc
DeleteIf you deny that things like coherence can be known objectively, then all realms of knowledge become relative.
Natural science faces similar issues. How do you know if a theory has been falsified or not? People will disagree on the interoperation of certain data,
DeleteIf a theory makes a prediction with regard to experiment or natural phenomenon that is later contradicted by experiments and/or observations, then the theory is falsified.
While it is true that sometimes multiple theories can explain the same set of data, and sometimes a theory supported by data may still be false or inaccurate, as the Ptolemaic system once made correct predictions, advances in technology have enabled us to perform experiments and observations which weren't possible before and which allow us to distinguish between theories, to separate the wheat from the chaff, so to speak. This correcting mechanism has made continuous progress in science possible. But I don't know of a similar mechanism in metaphysics, when it goes beyond logic and observation.
P.S. IF you wish to carry on the conversation with me, please attach a username to your message, so I can tell you apart from other Anonymouses on here.
Falsificationism seems dumb.
DeleteIf a theory is unfalsifiable, then what's stopping the theorist from picking up the theory and making it an axiom of his system?
While this might not work perfectly for all purposes, I would say that "false" and "incoherent" are different in that they apply to different kinds of wrongness. A statement that asserts a matter of fact is "false" if the actual fact - the real condition - is contrary to the statement's assertion. This is most clearly tested in specific claims of fact of physical factual matters: "the board has been cut into 2 pieces". If it's still one whole piece, or lying in 3 equal pieces, the assertion is properly understood as "false". This is NOT the same as saying the assertion is "incoherent". The assertion is entirely understandable, it just happens to not match the real facts. (In many cases, it could have matched the real facts, if the fact of the matter is contingent and could have been otherwise.)
DeleteIncoherence applies to a statement when its "meaning" (as a whole) cannot be held in the mind, either because one part of the statement contradicts another part of the statement, or because the parts can't be made to integrate as an intelligible statement. The classic example is "A square circle is (any X)," which is incoherent because "square" cannot modify circle. Or "A green justice will coagulate." is incoherent because "green" cannot modify "justice" and because "justice" cannot coagulate. But those are trivial.
The more interesting incoherence is the situation between different statements which cannot both be true at the same time. E.G. "The apple is wholly green" and "the apple is wholly red". The mind cannot hold BOTH to be true at the same time. In this pair, the contradiction is manifest, and for that reason the mind cannot hold both as true. That is, they cannot both cohere in the mind.
But if you have more obscure statements, or more complex ones that have many presuppositions built in, the impossibility of one being true if the other is true might not be immediately manifest. In that case, the incoherence would be rather a result of making manifest the contradiction by evoking directly contradictory implications. The base statements would still rightly be called "incoherent" as regards each other, but the incoherence would require an argument. E.G. Given Euclid's premises, it is not AT FIRST obvious that not both of these are possible: "This triangle's is a triangle," and "It's angles add up to 170 degrees". But the incoherence can be established by elaborated argument. At that point, the mind (should) recognize the incoherence of the two assertions as a pair. It would be a manifestation of a sick mind to NOT so recognize, after seeing (and understanding) the proof.
Basil Mitchell laid the criticism about falsification of metaphysics to rest.
DeleteTony,
DeleteNot sure if you're responding to my question, or just making a general comment. I don't have any objection to what you said.
I suspect that being coherent is already a great achievement for most metaphysicians. :) But, as you pointed out, a statement can be perfectly coherent but factually false. So my question is how metaphysicians determine the verity of their thesis, beyond logic and observation.
"There is also the attempt to resolve metaphysical questions by way of theology, which Gilson associates with thinkers like Bonaventure."
ReplyDeleteInteresting claim. Could we say this one is fair with St. Bonaventure itself?
Etienne Gilson embodied the best Thomistic approach to modernity. He was so good at getting to the roots of philosophical deviations from the early Renaissance onward. His work, Dante the Philosopher, explains the revolution against Thomism and the whole Christian Western worldview expressed in Alighieri's texts. Gilson was also alert to the dangers of nouvelle theologie Thomism, and Maritain's views. It's great to see Gilson remembered.
ReplyDeleteWell said. Gilson kept writing well into his mid 80s
DeleteWell said indeed. Gilson's scholarly output was prolific. I wasn't aware of his book on Dante, but not play to get it. It is remarkable that he also had monographs expounding the thought of Bonaventure, Scotus, Aquinas, and Augustine along with his History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. He also had a work treating modern philosophy and his dissertation on Descartes is high on my reading list. Scholasticism is better understood today largely because of the efforts of a single man and the founding of the Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies under his leadership.
DeleteOckham, Gilson argues, essentially tries to resolve metaphysical questions by appeal to human psychology.
ReplyDeleteThis is an anachronism, because psychology was founded in 1879 but Wilhelm of Ockham flourished in the early 14th century.
Uh, no. Psychology was studied for well over a millennium before the discipline of academic psychology was founded. Aquinas’ treatise on the passions is one of the most notable contributions to the genre.
DeleteSt. Thomas of Aquino was not the type of person who would have studied psychology. He would have thought it was the countess offering snake oil, draining your emotions and causing you to turn off your mind to external reality like Hatikoû [Kunrei-Shiki] or The Dog of Flanders.
DeleteIn conclusion, he would have judged it an abomination. Q.E.D.
William of Ockham was an English friar.
DeleteThomas wrote as master of thomistic psychology and epistemology.
DeleteSt. Thomas of Aquino was not the type of person who would have studied psychology.
DeletePsychology is the study of the (human) mind, and the interior human activities that the mind touches, e.g. feelings, emotions, choices, and so on. Like Aristotle before him, Aquinas most definitely dealt with these matters, extensively. The notion that "psychology was founded in 1879" entails a very narrow concept of psychology, one that discounts ancient efforts without basis.
Yes. Aristotle and his "De Anima."
DeleteDr. Feser,
ReplyDeleteHave you ever written your thoughts about Gilson’s Thomism contrasted with that of Lagrange? I have seen places where you mention the difference, and that you have thoughts, but, I have never seen a place where you express your thoughts at any length.
Merry Christmas Prof!
ReplyDeleteIt's been a wild year , I am grateful to have had you as an intellectual guiding light and as a unifying force for all the various aspects of my catholic world view. For that you have my sincere gratitude. I hope many graces are showered upon us this Christmas and everyone at the blog.
Cheers!