The wager
Pascal
begins with the assumption that unaided reason cannot establish one way or the
other whether God exists. I think he is
quite wrong about that, since I
hold that several of the traditional arguments for God’s existence are
compelling. But suppose, for the sake of
argument, that Pascal is correct. We still,
he holds, must “wager” over whether God exists, either betting that he does or
betting that he does not. Yet how can
reason decide what bet to make, if it cannot show whether it is theism or
atheism that is more likely to be true?
In its
simplest form, Pascal’s argument is this.
God either exists or he does not, and you can either bet that he does or
bet that he does not. Suppose you bet
that he exists, and it turns out that he really does. Then you will enjoy an infinite benefit,
eternal life in heaven. But suppose you
bet that he exists and it turns out that he does not. You will have been mistaken, but will have
suffered no loss. Of course, while
someone who regards a devout and moral life to be of value in itself will agree
with that, a more worldly person would not.
He would say that by mistakenly betting that God exists, he would
deprive himself of worldly pleasures he could have enjoyed. But even if one concedes this, Pascal holds,
what one will have lost is still of relatively small value, and certainly of
finite value.
Now suppose
that one bets that God does not exist, and that in fact he does not. Then, Pascal says, one will enjoy no gain
from this. Or, even if a worldly person
suggests that he will have gained worldly pleasures from it, this would still
be a relatively small gain, and certainly a finite gain. But suppose that one bets that God does not
exist and it turns out he is wrong – that God does in fact exist. Then,
says Pascal, he will suffer an infinite loss.
He will have lost out on the infinite reward of eternal life in heaven.
When we
consider this cost-benefit analysis, concludes Pascal, we can see that the only
rational wager to make is to bet that God exists. Now, Pascal is aware that one cannot simply and
suddenly make oneself believe in God,
the way one might make the lights go on by flipping a switch. But since it is reason that tells us to bet on God’s existence, the problem, he
concludes, must be with our passions. These are what prevent belief. And they can be changed by throwing oneself
into the religious life. Doing so will
gradually alter one’s passions, and in this way belief in God can be generated indirectly
even though it cannot be produced directly by a simple act of will.
Mackie’s critique
Against all
this, Mackie raises two main objections.
First, Pascal emphasizes that there is no affront to reason in his
argument, and indeed that wagering that God exists is what reason
dictates. But this, says Mackie, is not
the case, for Pascal’s advice to work up belief by way of molding one’s
passions amounts to recommending self-deception. Mackie notes that Pascal might respond by
saying that what one is trying to work oneself into is really what amounts to a
deeper wisdom or understanding. But
given Pascal’s own assumptions, argues Mackie, such a response would beg the
question. For whether belief in God does
in fact reflect wisdom or understanding about how the world really is is
precisely what Pascal acknowledges to be impossible to establish directly by rational
arguments.
Second, says
Mackie, Pascal’s argument can work only if the options we have to choose from
are two, belief that God exists or the absence of such belief. But in fact there are many more options than
that. We have to choose between Catholicism
versus Protestantism, Christianity versus Islam or Hinduism, theism versus
polytheism, and so on. And once we realize
that, we see that Pascal’s argument falls apart. No cost-benefit analysis of the issue is
going to give us anything like the crisp and clear advice he thinks it does.
Mackie’s
second criticism overstates the case somewhat.
For not every religious view entails that one risks suffering an
infinite loss by rejecting it. Only
religions that posit eternal damnation entail that. And for purposes of Pascal’s reasoning, one
need consider only religions of that kind, which narrows things down. Still, Mackie’s basic point remains that
there are more than just the two options considered by Pascal (since there is
more than one religion that posits eternal damnation).
Are Mackie’s
objections fatal? It seems to me that that
may depend on the epistemic situation of the person approaching Pascal’s wager
scenario. Suppose that, as far as you
know, there really are no good rational grounds at all for preferring any one
religion over another. Given the
evidence and argumentation available to you, none of them seems like a live
option, any more than believing in elves or witches does. In this case, Pascal’s Wager seems to have no
value, for the reasons Mackie gives. It
cannot by itself give you a reason to opt for one among the variety of available
religious options, and the exercise in artificially working up belief in one of
them would seem to entail irrationally “suppressing one’s critical faculties,”
as Mackie puts it (The Miracle of Theism,
p. 202). In short, as a strategy for
rationally persuading the most unsympathetic sort of agnostic or atheist,
Pascal’s Wager appears to fail.
Can it be salvaged?
However,
suppose one is in a very different epistemic situation. Suppose, for example, that one is not entirely
certain that the arguments for God’s existence, Jesus’s resurrection, and other
elements of Christian doctrine are correct, but still judges them to be strong
and thinks that Christianity is at least very plausible. Suppose that one considers further that among
these doctrines is the teaching on original sin, according to which our
rational and moral faculties have been damaged in such a way that it is much
less easy for us to see the truth, or to even want to see it, than it would
have been had we not suffered original sin’s effects. Then one might judge that it may be that
while he regards the evidences for Christianity to be strong, the reason he nevertheless
remains uncertain is due to the damage his intellect and will have suffered as
a result of original sin.
His
situation would be comparable to someone who judges that he is suffering from
chronic delusions and hallucinations, like John Nash as portrayed by Russell
Crowe in the movie version of A Beautiful
Mind. Nash has good reasons for
holding that some of things he is inclined to believe and thinks that he sees
are illusory. Yet he finds he nevertheless
cannot help but continue to see these things and be drawn to these paranoid beliefs. Since, overall, the most plausible interpretation
of the situation is that these nagging beliefs and experiences are delusional,
he decides to refuse to take them seriously and to keep ignoring them until
they go away, or at least until they have less attraction for him. This is not contrary to reason, but rather
precisely a way to restore reason to its proper functioning.
Similarly,
the potential religious believer in my scenario judges that he has good reason
to think that Christianity really is true, even though he is also nevertheless uncertain
about it. And he also judges that he has
good reason to suspect that his lingering doubts may be due to the weaknesses
of his intellect and will that are among the effects of original sin. Suppose, then, that he appeals to something
like Pascal’s Wager as a way of resolving the doubts. He judges that Christianity is plausible
enough that he would suffer little or no loss if he believed in it but turned
out to be mistaken, and little or no benefit if he disbelieved in it and turned
out to be correct. And he also judges it
plausible that the potential reward for believing would be infinite, and the
potential loss for disbelief also infinite.
So, he wagers that Christianity is true.
Like Nash in
A Beautiful Mind, he resolves to
ignore any nagging doubts to the contrary, throwing himself into the religious
life and thereby molding his passions and cognitive inclinations until the
doubts go away or at least become less troublesome. And like Nash, he judges that this is in no
way contrary to reason, but rather precisely a way of restoring reason to its
proper functioning (given that the doubts are, he suspects, due to the
lingering effects of original sin).
In this sort
of scenario, then, it’s not that the Wager by itself takes someone from initially
finding God’s existence in no way likely, all the way to having a rational belief
in God’s existence. That, as I’ve agreed
with Mackie, is not plausible. Rather,
in my imagined scenario, reason has already taken the person up to the
threshold of a solid conviction that God exists, and the Wager simply pushes
him over it.
No doubt, even this attributes to reason a greater efficacy in deciding about theological matters than Pascal himself would have been willing to acknowledge. But, tentatively, I judge it the most plausible way for the Pascalian to try to defend something like the Wager argument, at least against Mackie’s objections. (And I don’t claim more for it than that. Naturally, there is a larger literature on the argument that I do not pretend to have addressed here.)
I've yet to see a good explanation as to why such self-deception (as Mackie accuses Pascal's Wager of encouraging) is an intrinsically bad thing on naturalistic atheism. If it provides hope, comfort, community, and a basic moral framework with which to live my life, Christianity might well prove to be a rather useful and desirable delusion.
ReplyDeleteYou end up in this strange situation where if atheism is false, you ought to disbelieve it, but if it is true, then you still probably ought to disbelieve it (though for somewhat different reasons).
And sure, props to those who stand on principle and try to align themselves with the truth. But for those inclined toward a naturalistic worldview I have to ask: In this particular case, why bother? It certainly can't be because truth, as such, is important.
The reason why one would decide that self-deception is bad from an atheistic perspective is pretty simple: the gnawing suspicion that you're being conned.
DeleteSecular history teaches history as a series of charismatic charlatans who swayed the masses into believing in falsehoods that prevented them from acting according to their rational self-interest. If you are a convinced atheist-materialist, you have to come to the conclusion that the vast majority of humanity was just wrong about important metaphysical and moral questions. This naturally recommends a hermaneutic of suspicion in regards to these topics - people who disagree with you aren't just wrong, they're looking to get one over on you. You can't trust "common sense" or "received wisdom", as that's only what those in charge are telling you to think.
This is, I think, a motivating factor in why these atheists care so much about truth as a concept: they are afraid of being tricked.
You need God to provide a basic moral framework? You can’t figure out on your own what’s wrong with say, acting like Jeffery Dahmer??
DeleteLewis illustrates this beautifully in The Last Battle: "The dwarfs are for the dwarfs!"
DeleteSecular history teaches history as a series of charismatic charlatans who swayed the masses into believing in falsehoods that prevented them from acting according to their rational self-interest.
DeleteThat can be turned just as easily on the materialistic rationalist charlatans whose just so stories concocted of evolution and "we know not what" imaginary intermediate steps are used to con the masses to give up religion.
You need God to provide a basic moral framework? You can’t figure out on your own what’s wrong with say, acting like Jeffery Dahmer??
DeleteThe "basic moral framework" wasn't meant to be in contrast to "no moral framework" but rather to the patchwork and inchoate moral framework that most people develop when left to their own devices. Say what you will about Christian (especially Catholic) morality, it at least has a few thousand years of thought to make it refined and relatively applicable.
If you're going through life simply figuring things out as you go, there are going to be consequent disadvantages.
Excellent article, Dr. Feser! Correct me if I'm wrong, but I've always thought that Mackie's objection of question-begging itself begs the question. While Pascal's entire argument, from each step, is really just presenting the best course of action while operating under epistemic uncertainty vis-a-vis God's existence, Mackie's objection only holds if God certainly does not exist. Doesn't this beg the question in his favor?
ReplyDeleteExcellent. Agreed. Thank you.
ReplyDeletePascal’s Wager is essential not at the last step but at the first. What reason cannot prove is that we live in a reasonable universe. We cannot know that everything is not just chaos that happens to look this way out of dumb luck. If you see 100 coins that are all head up, you cannot prove that they weren’t all thrown in the air and landed that way, no matter how unlikely that is. Pascal’s wager is what gets you over this first step.
ReplyDeleteThe first argument is silly because Pascal’s wager cannot prove to you that Catholic Christianity is true, even if you were at a threshold point. But if the idea of a specific religion is dropped entirely, if what you are betting on is that the universe at root makes sense and is not a random assortment of atoms, Pascal’s wager is precisely what you need.
I fail to understand Mackie's first objection. Perhaps, because I don't fully understand Pascal's Wager.
ReplyDeleteMy understanding is that a rational man must choose whether to live his life as if God exists or as if God does not exist. This choice is forced. A man cannot avoid it. If he finds the arguments for the existence of God unconvincing, he then confronts Pascal's Wager, an eternity in heaven outweighs a lifetime of worldly pleasures, no matter the relative likelihood of God's nonexistence. Therefore a rational man would choose to live his life as if God exists in the expectation that his belief would eventually conform to his practice. So, then the rational man following this argument can forsee that though at present he is ambivalent about the existence of God, he will come in the future to believe in the existence of God and such a belief will be rational.
So, what is Mackie's first objection? Is it merely that Pascal's Wager is only about belief and not about how a man lives his life? And thus no choice ought to be made? This seems strange given that the Wager concerns eternal life versus worldly pleasures. Again, I fail to understand Mackie's first objection.
Let me add a small note. Here I have put the cart (living one's life) before the horse (the wager) in order to emphasize that the both the horse and the cart are part of the argument, though traditionally the horse is emphasized and the cart is not (and even occasionally omitted). Perhaps I am wrong and completely misunderstood my professors.
WCB
ReplyDeleteBetting on God's existence is not good enough. Islam claims God has no son and to claim that dooms one to hell. Christianity claims if we deny Jesus is the son of God, we are damned. Or maybe the right religion is Mormons, or Hinduism.
Then suppose one chooses Christianity. Just believing is not good enough, one must follow the commands of Jesus.
Mark 10:21, Luke 12:32-33, Luke 14:33, Luke 18:23, Matthew 19:20-21, Matthew 6:24-25
Sell all you have and give to the poor.
WCB
The first command was given to one particular individual, the second was given to the disciples *when the kingdom was imminent (see also its reoffer in Acts 3:19-21 and the relevant actions in Acts 4:34-35)* the third Lk 14:33 is the same (though notice a possible alternative in the immediately preceding verse 32, the fourth parallels the first, the fifth ie Matthew 19:20-21 as with the first and the fourth, the last just condemns *love of* money.
DeleteWCB
DeleteLuke 14
33 So likewise, whosoever he be of you that forsaketh not all that he hath, he cannot be my disciple.
WCB
Indeed, but see previous verse.
DeleteAlso note Matthew 10:5-6 and 15:21-28 - are these for today?
I feel that a proper argument from Mackie (and Pascal, for that matter) would entail discussing what we mean by "belief", and make sure we are not using different definitions or senses - which almost certainly happens outside of rigorous circles. As I recall from my past theology reading, the Christian take on belief to propositions (when it is just considered in general, and not specially applied to God), it is a kind of assent to the propositions where the assent is firm, stable, even "definitive", and that the firmness of this assent exceeds the firmness of the evidence. If the assent has the firmness of certainty because you have rigorous proof, that's not belief, that's "knowledge". When it an unstable assent held as capable of being changed, that's "opinion" (or some other lesser things, like "guess" and "suspicion" etc.)
ReplyDeleteNow, using Mackie's initial point to impose a little caution on Pascal, one might argue that if the world is such that it is impossible for the evidence to prove one way or another on whether God exists, it is entirely feasible to simply CONTINUE to hold that the evidence is inconclusive and deny that the nature of the world REQUIRES I hold a judgment with greater firmness than "I am not certain". One may remain uncertain without affront to the universe; and if God is the one who made the universe that way, then also without affront to God.
I think that there are potential gaps in this also, but they require a deeper understanding of how belief functions in human beings, and in particular an understanding that belief about some things is a normal part of life, and total skepticism is not. As an example, I believe in my wife and in her faithful commitment to me, though it is not susceptible of rigorous, absolute proof. Life entails belief, and this implies that belief as a category is not a "contra-rational, improper" mental act per se. It is (in the proper conditions) extra-rational by going beyond the evidence, but it doesn't defy reason; you are not called to believe when the sum total of the evidence says "no, this is extremely improbable!"
Taking Feser's point above about how original sin damaged us, and putting that together with a truth that is (at least) highly probable, that the human person is made for love, one runs up against this: if our ultimate, comprehensive and highest end is love, it must be love of a something fit for our highest and most comprehensive love. In this situation, it not sufficient for us to hold an ultimate being is "probable, but not certain because the evidence isn't quite conclusive yet". We have no option but to seek for the highest good that can be loved, and we can't fully love him on the basis of probability.
I also tend to think that "belief" in this context is under defined.
DeleteThe kind of conviction we often associate with religious belief doesn't even necessarily make sense when applied to other areas. If I am a person with a severe phobia of flying and yet I decide to board a plane anyway, do I believe that the plane is going to crash or not?
It certainly seems that in that scenario I have an affectual conviction that flying is going to cause something bad to happen to me from my phobia. Am I engaging in self-deception by ignoring that and choosing to fly anyway? I sort of doubt that Mackie would think so.
Say what you will about Mackie's views, he was at least able to disagree amicably.
ReplyDelete"Mackie is said to have been capable of expressing total disagreement in such a genial way that the person being addressed might mistake his comment for a compliment.[10] This personal style is exemplified by the following words from the preface to Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong:
I am nowhere mainly concerned to refute any individual writer. I believe that all those to whom I have referred, even those with whom I disagree most strongly, have contributed significantly to our understanding of ethics: where I have quoted their actual words, it is because they have presented views or arguments more clearly or more forcefully than I could put them myself.[11]"
In response to the Many God's objection, you could just say choose the version of theism you fond most plausible. However, my big issue with Pascal's Wager is it would make a lot more sense for God to prefer you to honestly evaluate the arguments rather than convince yourself it is true for selfish benefit. Feser's way of reframing into something that can help a person overcome their doubts after concluding that it is plausible seems to deal with this objection.
ReplyDeletePascal's Provincial Letters suggests that he was aware of the necessity of reason but it's insufficiency when he satirizes the Molinists.
ReplyDeleteHe does this in a most amusing way
Pascal embodies the deep scepticism of the conservative Enlightenment, which was so corrosive to Christian belief. His ideas never detached themselves from the Jansenism pervasive in France. This cancer only came to an end when the French revolution destroyed the Ancien Regime systems in France and elsewhere (which were the first institutional embodiments of the Enlightenment), permitting the Church, from Pius VI onwards, to reaffirm scholasticism, the Church as wholly free institution distinct from civil society, culminating in that great expression of Catholic rationalism and freedom from social absolutism, the First Vatican Council.
ReplyDeleteWhy won’t Jesus just send down fire from the sky in response to prayers asking him to do so, like for the prophet Elijah, this ending atheism once and for all?
ReplyDeleteThat will happen at the Last Judgment.
DeleteAmen.
DeleteBut then it would be too late!
DeleteYes.
DeleteIt seems to me that part of the issue with Pascal's wager is an implicit Protestant kind of soteriology.
ReplyDeleteWhen you are wagering that you have to force yourself to believe in something you don't really, I am sympathetic to Mackie's first objection. But when taking the wager instead is something more like "act in a way according to how a particular system you aren't necessarily sold on as though it is true" is not obviously self-deception in the same way.
Folks, I think Ed made a very important point about original sin that, even if someone agrees with it or not, is crucial to our lives as human beings i.e. we must acknowledge our limitations and be humble to know our limits. Sometimes the best solution to our dilemmas (whether philosophical or theological) is to be humble and accept that we are limited, that we are sometimes (if not, most times) incapable of arriving at what we really want to know -- in the exact way we want to know -- by ourselves, due to our limited intellects.
ReplyDeleteIt is no shame to admit that we are most of the time incapable of arriving at significant truths, and, that this lack of knowledge can hurt us from the inside (either it be by causing anxiety, feelings of diminishment, agony, and so on). But, on the other hand, perhaps we can follow what is most probably true and send away the lingering doubts and unsolved questions that afflict our hearts.
I think that the key to achieving this is to let go of the hubris we all carry in some way or other. When I was 20 years old, for example, I thought I could figure out the world around me since I was "so smart," till I finally faced the fact some years later that I was helpless and incapable of knowing most of the world out there alone (and added to that, when I acknowledged that some fellas that lived 3200 years or so before got the whole metaphysical picture better than me, a so-called "modern man," really humbled me).
In all of that, we all also must recognize that Ed brought this lesson in a way a lot of us (myself included) could never expect i.e. through a post about Pascal's wager! We also must be thankful to him for bringing this important lesson to us through his blog. Sometimes God blesses us with intelligent people who help us go beyond our intellectual limitations -- and no doubt I think Ed is one of these people -- to achieve something meaningful.
So, let's all meditate and think about this meaningful insight instead of focusing on quibbles or matters that are, at best, beside the point.
https://www.hawking.org.uk/in-words/lectures/godel-and-the-end-of-physics
ReplyDeleteThank you for your X about Job. It touched me deeply.
ReplyDelete