Ordinarily,
of course, it is wrong to inflict bodily harm on someone. But not always. It can be permissible and sometimes even
obligatory to do so – for example, in self-defense or in punishment of a crime. It is not inflicting bodily harm per se that is bad, but rather
inflicting it on someone who does not deserve it. The difference between the guilty and the
innocent is crucial. Bank robbers shooting
at police and the police who fire back at them are inflicting the same sort of
harm on each other, but they are not morally on a par. The robbers are doing something evil but the
police are doing something good, namely defending themselves and others from
the evildoing of the robbers.
Something
analogous can be said about the harm we inflict with words. Ordinarily we should avoid this, but not
always. Sometimes a person deserves such
harm, and in some cases we do good by inflicting it. Thus Aquinas writes:
Just as it is lawful to strike a person, or damnify him in
his belongings for the purpose of correction, so too, for the purpose of
correction, may one say a mocking word to a person whom one has to correct. It is thus that our Lord called the disciples
“foolish,” and the Apostle called the Galatians “senseless.” Yet, as Augustine says (De Serm. Dom. in Monte ii, 19), “seldom and only when it is very
necessary should we have recourse to invectives, and then so as to urge God's
service, not our own.” (Summa Theologiae
II-II.72.2)
Naturally,
there are some harms we inflict through words that are never permissible. For example, calumny involves damaging someone’s reputation by spreading
falsehoods about him. This is always and
intrinsically wrong. But there are
harmful words of other kinds that are not always and intrinsically wrong.
Two kinds in
particular are especially relevant to public debate about matters of politics,
philosophy, theology, and the like.
There are, first of all, public insults and mockery of the kind that may
decrease the honor or esteem in which another person is held. And second, there is the public dissemination
of truths about another person that tend to damage his reputation. When insults and mockery of the sort in
question are not deserved, they amount to what moral theologians call the sin
of contumely. When such damage to a person’s reputation is
not deserved, it amounts to what is called the sin of detraction.
Needless to
say, the sins of contumely and detraction are extremely common in public debate
– perhaps more common today than ever before, given the rise of the
internet. But sometimes a person may
deserve to be spoken of in ways that dishonor him or damage his reputation, and
sometimes the public good may even be served by such speech. In these cases, such harmful words do not
amount to contumely or detraction, any more than a policemen’s killing a bank
robber who shoots at him amounts to murder.
Hence, in
his treatment of detraction, Aquinas holds that “if it is for the sake of something
good or necessary that someone utters words by which someone else’s reputation
is diminished, then, as long as the right circumstances are preserved, this is
not a sin and cannot be called detraction” (Summa
Theologiae II-II.73.2, Freddoso
translation). For example, “it
is not detraction to reveal someone’s hidden sin by denouncing him for the sake
of his improvement or by accusing him for the sake of the good of public justice.” Similarly, moral theologians John McHugh and
Charles Callan note that “the public good is to be preferred to a false
reputation, for the public welfare is the ground for the right to such
reputation, the subject himself being unworthy of the good name he bears” (Moral Theology, Volume II, p. 243). Hence, there is nothing wrong with revealing
someone’s criminal behavior to authorities or to those who might be harmed by
it, or with warning consumers of fraudulent business practices.
In general,
though a good person has an absolute right to a good reputation, there is no
absolute right to such a reputation among those who do not deserve it. As McHugh and Callan write:
The right to a false reputation is a relative and limited
right, one which ceases when the common good on which it rests no longer
supports it (e.g. when it cannot be maintained without injustice). Moreover, there is no right to an
extraordinary reputation, if it is based on false premises, for the common good
does not require such a right, and hence it is not detraction to show that the
renown of an individual for superior skill or success is built up on
advertising alone or merely on uninformed rumor. (p. 225)
For example,
it is not detraction to point out that a commentator well-known for his
opinions about some topic (political, scientific, philosophical, theological,
or whatever) in fact is not competent to speak about it and that his views have
little value. Even if this damages his
reputation, there is no sin of detraction, because no one has a right to a reputation for some excellence
that in fact he lacks. It can even be obligatory
for those who do have the relevant expertise to call attention to such a
person’s incompetence, lest those who don’t know any better are misled by him.
Similarly, as
Aquinas says in the first passage from the Summa
quoted above, it is not always sinful, and indeed can even be necessary, to
deploy insult or mockery. McHugh and Callan
note that “those are not guilty of contumely who speak words that are not
honorable to persons deserving of reproof” (p. 211). Naturally, people who deserve it would
include those who are themselves guilty of detraction or contumely. McHugh and Callan hold that in self-defense
against such verbal attacks, “it is lawful to deny the charge, or by retort to
turn the tables on the assailant” (p. 216).
It is true
that in some cases it can be virtuous simply to remain humbly silent in the
face of detraction or contumely. But
this is not always necessary or advisable.
McHugh and Callan write:
One should repel contumely when there are good and sufficient
reasons for this course, and hence Our Lord… refuted those who decried Him as a
blasphemer, or glutton, or demoniac, or political disturber…
The good of the offender, in order that his boldness be
subdued and that he be deterred from such injuries in the future, is a
sufficient reason. Hence the words of
Proverbs (xxvi. 5) that one should answer a fool, lest he think himself wise.
The good of others is another reason, in order that they be
not demoralized by the vilification of one whom they have looked up to as an
example and guide, especially if silence will appear to be a sign of weakness
or carelessness or guilt. Hence, St.
Gregory says that preachers should answer detractors, lest the Word of God be
without fruit.
The good of self is a third reason for replying to contumely,
for to enjoy the respect and esteem of others helps many a good person to act
worthily of the opinion in which he is held, and it restrains many a sinner
from descending to worse things than those of which he is guilty. (pp. 215-16)
It is no
surprise, then, that scripture and Church history are full of saints who
deployed verbal attacks when engaging with their enemies. Elijah mocked the priests of Baal (1 Kings
18:27). St. John the Baptist called the
Pharisees and Sadducees a “brood of vipers” (Matthew 3:7). Christ Himself condemned the scribes and
Pharisees as “whitewashed tombs” whose false outward piety disguised an inner
“filthiness” (Matthew 23:27). St. Paul
pilloried Elymas the magician as a “son of the devil, enemy of all
righteousness, full of all deceit and villainy” (Acts 13:10). St. Jerome was well-known for his invective. St. Thomas More criticized
Martin Luther with vituperation so extreme that some of it could not
be quoted in a family publication. And
so on.
Of course,
by no means does this entail that “anything goes.” Again, calumny is absolutely ruled out, no
matter who the target is. And even when
deployed against wrongdoers, verbal attacks that are excessive or motivated by
a vengeful spirit rather than defense of the good would amount to detraction or
contumely and thus be sinful. The point,
though, is that it would be a mistake to suppose that those who fight invective
with invective are necessarily no
better than those they are responding to.
That would be like supposing that police who return fire at bank robbers
are no better than the bank robbers. It
ignores the crucial distinctions between the guilty and the innocent, and
between the aggressor and the defender.
It can be
especially appropriate to employ insulting and otherwise harsh language when
dealing with those who both promote bad ideas and are themselves gratuitously
abusive in their dealings with others. And
that is not merely because they deserve such tit-for-tat. It is because a softer approach is often
simply ineffective in countering their errors.
Sometimes a bully will not be stopped by anything but a punch in the
nose. And when the bullying takes the
form of invective, the punch in the nose should take the same form.
Consider the
New Atheist movement, now pretty much dead but once very influential. As I showed in my book The Last Superstition: A Refutation of
the New Atheism, the arguments of New Atheist writers like Richard
Dawkins and Sam Harris were laughably sophomoric. But they were presented with supreme
self-confidence, and dripped with condescension and contempt for the religious
thinkers who were their targets. Hence,
though the New Atheism’s intellectual content was extremely thin, its polemical
style gave it a rhetorical force that could be intimidating to many.
When
responding to such polemics, it is insufficient politely to point out fallacies
and errors of fact. For it isn’t the intellectual
quality of the arguments that is doing the main work in the first place, but
rather the aggressive and self-assured tone.
To leave that unrebutted is to leave the façade largely intact. No matter how carefully you explain why an
argument is no good, many readers will still retain the impression that if it
is presented with such arrogant self-confidence, it must have something going for it. A weak case can convince many simply on the
strength of the unearned prestige of the person presenting it. Hence that prestige must be lowered by
deploying against it the same sort of rhetoric that created it.
Note that
this does not involve any ad hominem
fallacy. An ad hominem fallacy involves attacking a person instead of attacking some claim or argument the person made, while at
the same time pretending that one has thereby refuted the claim or argument
itself. That is not what I am talking
about. Of course one must, first and
foremost, refute the claims and arguments themselves. What I am saying is that in addition to doing that, one must sometimes attack the credibility
of the person, when that credibility is illusory but will lead his listeners
wrongly to take his views seriously. (I
say more here
about what an ad hominem fallacy is
and what it is not.)
Hence, my
approach in The Last Superstition was
to deploy against the New Atheists superior intellectual firepower coupled with
equal and opposite rhetorical force. I
have over the years dealt with various other sophists, blowhards, and bullies
in the same fashion. I make no apologies
for that, because such treatment is justifiable in light of the principles I’ve
been setting out here. But by no means
do I, or would I, take this approach with others with whom I disagree. Mostly it’s uncalled for and unnecessary.
Occasionally
I’m nevertheless accused of being too frequently aggressive in style. That this is not true is something for which
there is some objective evidence. Of the
fourteen books I’ve written, co-written, or edited, exactly one is written in the polemical style in
question – namely, The Last Superstition. Of the over 250 articles I’ve
published (academic and popular articles, book reviews and the like), only about
15% are in that style. I’ve also written
well over 1500 blog posts, and while it would take more time than I’m willing
to spend to determine the percentage of polemical articles among them, I’d
wager that it’s about the same.
In any event, usually the people who fling the accusation are themselves routinely vituperative, or are fans of some vituperative writer to whom I’ve responded in kind. Though the “sticks and stones” cliché isn’t true, another well-known saying certainly is: Those who like to dish it out often can’t take it.
Well said, Prof.
ReplyDeleteIf I screenshot your tweets and quotes from this blog to my WhatsApp status, you don't mind, right Prof ? Tweets have your name , but blog posts screenshots I mention it below because after all you have the right to your good reputation for those quotes of wisdom! :)
DeleteHi Norm, no problem
DeleteHey Ed -- nice article, might want to run a spell-check for the word "pubic" in your piece. ;)
ReplyDeleteCheers,
-- AKruger
Yikes, fixed it, thanks!
DeleteIn a tweet, you mentioned the Freddoso translation of ST, and I see you use it here. I'd be interested to hear your (and others') thoughts on how it compares with that of the Fathers of the English Dominican Province.
ReplyDeleteI really like this English/Latin translation:
Deletehttps://aquinas.cc/la/en/~ST.I
I believe there are cases where Fred's translation is a bit more accurate (though specific examples elude my memory at the moment), but mostly I find that I sometimes prefer it because it's a bit more readable or contemporary in expression, while losing none of the dignity of the other translation
DeleteA good, if not particularly central, example of Freddoso's translation being vastly superior to the Dominican Fathers translation is at ST 2-2.96.1 (on the notory art, which is a specific form of magic concerned with trying to use symbolic invocations of angels to improve learning). The Dominican Fathers version that is available at New Advent (i.e., the online one that most people use) is very bad, mangling the entire article; there was a later edition of the Dominican Fathers that cleaned up this article in particular a bit, but is still not particularly great, because much of the point of the argument is still lost due to generic choices. Freddoso's is much better because (1) he recognizes that 'ars notoria' is a technical term and (2) St. Thomas is using the occasion to make points about appropriate way to learn things.
DeleteMost of the time, you don't get mistakes quite like that; the Dominican Fathers translation is usually very good. But it is also quite uneven, and across the whole book wavers quite a bit on the entire spectrum between woodenly literal renderings and highly paraphrastic renderings, which can interfere with particular things you might need to do with the text. One advantage Freddoso has, is the ability to be much more consistent in his translation choices.
I'm reading through the two translations now, and Freddoso seems far clearer. His language is less clunky, he uses fewer words where he can, and (mercifully) he numbers St Thomas's many lists. He gives the Latin word where helpful.
DeleteHere's an example from Freddoso, followed by one from the D.F. (I.81):
"Similarly, a natural necessity is not at odds with the will, either. At the very least, it is necessary that just as the intellect adheres by necessity to its first principles, so too the will adheres by necessity to its final end, which is beatitude. For as Physics 2 says, the end plays the role in matters of action (in operativis) that a [first] principle plays in speculative matters (in speculativis). For what belongs to something naturally and immutably must be the foundation and source (fundamentum et principium) of everything else, since in each thing what is primary is its nature, and all movement proceeds from something immovable."
"In like manner neither is natural necessity repugnant to the will. Indeed, more than this, for as the intellect of necessity adheres to the first principles, the will must of necessity adhere to the last end, which is happiness: since the end is in practical matters what the principle is in speculative matters. For what befits a thing naturally and immovably must be the root and principle of all else appertaining thereto, since the nature of a thing is the first in everything, and every movement arises from something immovable."
"Occasionally I’m nevertheless accused of being too frequently aggressive in style."
ReplyDeleteI think that is an unfair accusation. One thing is to be emphatic and direct and another to be aggressive. I think Ed's distinctive way is to be emphatic and direct -- that's what makes him so good and comprehensible to read, straight to the point, and so on.
On the other hand, I must say that I really miss the tone taken in TLS. I think that Dawkins still feels the sting of "not knowing the difference between metaphysics from Metamucil" to this day -- and he surely deserved that!
Maybe one day I'll write another book in that style. H. L. Mencken used to cackle at his own quips as he wrote, and I found myself doing so as I wrote TLS (and at some of the other more acerbic things I've written). One has to be careful not to get carried away by writing something too mean simply because it's funny. (I've cut things out before that I thought were funny but too harsh.)
Delete“Morally permissible “ and “effective” are not the same thing. Back when I was a Christian, seeing someone on yahoo answers whose avatar was Jesus fish roasting on a bbq was offensive and only made me feel disrespect towards that person.
ReplyDeleteFurthermore, if you go on Amazon and read the 3 and under star reviews of ThebLast Superstition, the critics almost all focus on the condescending tone of the book!
ReplyDeleteSimilarly, moral theologians John McHugh and Charles Callan note that “the public good is to be preferred to a false reputation, for the public welfare is the ground for the right to such reputation, the subject himself being unworthy of the good name he bears”... The right to a false reputation is a relative and limited right, one which ceases when the common good on which it rests no longer supports it (e.g. when it cannot be maintained without injustice)."
ReplyDeleteUsually the expression is given as a "right to a good reputation" (not a false one), and the tension arises with the "right" so-called to not be held to account in public for "private" sins. We would all be made highly uncomfortable if ALL of our sins were known by everyone around us, and (so the argument goes) the social sphere is better served when not all sins are known by all, and thus arises the distinction of "public" sins vs "private" sins.
I would first note that no sin is held privately away from God, and all sins detract from the communion of saints by your loss of perfection, so already the idea of a "private sin" has some chips in it. Secondly, many sins (especially those that are also civil crimes) are clearly of a kind that they are usually committed in private, without any observers, but by their nature directly damage others, e.g. burglary. Those cannot be considered private. Thirdly, some sins damage other persons mainly indirectly, but do so in such a grave matter that the public aspect still is important, e.g. paying for pornography.
Many years ago, in what was considered a good diocese, a priest apparently became enamored of one of his married flock, committed adultery, and ended up leaving the parish, moving out of state, and "marrying" her. The diocese's initial bulletin was that he was "on sabbatical" or some such. As I recall, same diocese, another pastor was alleged to have taken parish money and spent it on porn, and the diocese's response (after removing him as pastor) explicitly rejected the position that the faithful had a right to know whether the priest rejected the allegation, or whether it was (or could have been) independently substantiated, asserting that he had a right to his good reputation. The bishop explained his reasons (in part) based on the requirement that people not make rash judgment about others' characters.
I would argue that in both cases, the sins (and crimes) alleged are essentially not of the sort that the priest gets to retain his good reputation if the actual facts were contrary to a good reputation, in that there are important public aspects of those actions which are necessary to rightly forming a public reputation about the men. Canon 1741.3 expressly allows for a bishop to remove a pastor because of the loss of a good reputation among upright and responsible parishioners , as a separate cause of removal from those reprehensible acts (like embezzlement) that violate his role. This implies that these "upright" parishioners can form judgments of reputability on reasonable evidence, and without rashness, decide that the guy doesn't deserve a good reputation. It isn't rash if they are upright, even if the knowledge of the facts has not yet been arisen to strict proof in a court of law as civil law violations. (And the standard of proof in law as regards criminal violations, from which can be imposed legal sanctions, is a different standard of certainty than rightly used for social purposes. You don't have to KNOW that a person has been convicted of fraud to decide not to contract for his services, after deciding that the allegations are reasonable enough for you to withhold your custom from him.)
I was just thinking about this in relation to Trump’s famous “Only Rosie O’Donnell” retort. I feel like that possibly met the requirements of this article. In fact Trump’s general demeanor, while often excessive, does demonstrate that even a less conservative politician can get more conservative results by having the right attitude. Conservatives are often too nice and therefore impotent.
ReplyDeleteHello Anon, I think his various remarks are a mixed bag. Sometimes they are very funny and his targets deserve it, and sometimes he goes too far. As a general rule, I think that making insulting public remarks about a woman's looks is wrong, whoever she is
DeleteI want to ask a question of Professor Feser regarding this topic.
ReplyDeleteSay you have well-known atheists who go around saying things to the effect of "If you were really a Christian, you would support my brand of liberal politics" or "You're not a good Christian because you enjoy comic books with scantily-clad female characters" or something to that effect.
What would you say in response to those kinds of people? For my money, they are certainly guilty of some kind of detraction, if not outright calumny in addition to distorting the truth. Is is sufficient to tell them that they don't know what they're talking about?
Well, I don't think that would necessarily count as detraction or calumny, as opposed to simply being a mistaken inference. If they coupled it with insults, it might be contumely
DeleteWolverine looks like Saitama from One Punch Man.
ReplyDeleteDictionary Image of overcompensating idiot.
What do you think about saying ”Richard Dawkins may be a good biologist, but as a philosopher he is completely worthless.” Is that to mean, or is it just the right thing to say?
ReplyDeleteIt was the right thing to say, given his own tone together with the points I made in the article. Also, it is factually accurate.
DeleteI did not even know that you have said that :-) The reason I asked the question is that I am thinking about saying it myself. Thanks for your answer.
DeleteI don't remember my exact words, but certainly statements to that effect can be found in The Last Superstition. ;-)
DeleteWhat if someone, in private, shares with another person that he’s been struggling with some personal vice, and then the person goes and starts gossiping about it?
ReplyDeleteA facile and self-serving post which amounts to, “I can attack other people because I’m good and they’re not. Oh, and anyone who accuses me of being “vituperative” is just projecting.” This is not a serious argument.
ReplyDeleteAlso, the word count on this post could be cut by at least a third if you dropped all the pompous verbiage (not to mention tone) and just got to the point. And vituperative twice in one sentence?
It obviously does not amount to that, since I gave arguments rather than merely making assertions -- arguments you simply ignore -- and the arguments are completely general rather than geared merely to defending anything that I, specifically, have written.
Delete(Kept it brief and non-vituperative for you!)
Thoughts on what I said about three star and under reviews of the last superstition?
DeleteAnonymous: makes it clear he thinks using invective is wrong
DeleteAlso Anonymous: uses invective to criticize Dr. Feser
Oh the irony...
Still hoping for an answer.
DeleteOn the one hand, we have the ethics of invective.
ReplyDeleteOn the other hand, one might call forceful condemnations of immorality or forceful propounding of morality the invective of ethics.
There's the Grapes of Wrath, and then there's the wrath of grapes (hangover).
DeleteThat's a good one.
DeleteIf our society is going to be converted, we are going to need more people that write with the force of Jerome or of Augustine against the Pelagians, Donatists and Manicures. I am grateful both for the substance, clarity and rigor of your work Dr Feser and for the force of your refutation of the New Atheists in TLS. They richly merited and it confirmed those that were doubting in the face of the New Atheist sophistry.
ReplyDeleteMichael,
DeleteThe "Manicures"?
I heard there are some still around....hanging on by their fingernails :-)
Bmiller,
DeleteLol! That is good while my typing on my phone for comments is bad!
I hear millions in the Muslim world have read Dawkins’ The God Delusion, in recent times, and it’s played a big role in their embrace of secularism.
ReplyDeleteI've often noticed that people who attack others viciously, but with shallow arguments, like the New Atheists did against Christians, are especially prone to crying about aggressiveness, when met with superior argumentative force combined with equally harsh and, perhaps, more stylistically apt rhetoric.
ReplyDeleteNot to brag, but given that I've spent a good amount of time debating, formally and informally, I know how to respond to such attacks, both in substance and in style if I mean to. The same guys who started the verbal aggression, thinking that it would work, then start crying about me being too agressive. Sometimes, it made me reexamine myself and consider if my style is just too aggressive, but I've realized during the years, that such people are just cowards and bullies: they want to attack without being attacked back.
I'd say that such a dynamic exists nowadays, broadly and generally (but not always), in the West between progressives and conservatives, seculars and Christians. A lot of Christians are just too afraid of being too aggressive, because the bullies who want to attack them and receive no attacks back largely control the narrative.
Just came across Timothy Gordon's twitter feed.
ReplyDeleteI think the way in which he uses derogatory terms like f****t, uplifts figures like Nick Fuentes, and is then upheld as an example of a ideal catholic, warmly welcomed by other respected traditionalists is very sad and unfortunate to say the least.
I think the actions of both these figures would rightly be classified as disturbing, unnecessary rhetoric and use of words.
It's completely the opposite of Dr Feser's measured, stern but charitable style.
They exemplify the common caricature of traditionalists, who are only a minority in traditionalist circles but nevertheless a loud minority that will have to be properly addressed in the future.
This has me wondering what your take would be on the debate between the Christian Andrew Wilson (whose style can be quite abrasive) versus the atheist Matt Dillahunty. Wilson kept up with some invective about transgender people being "deranged lunatics" and eventually ticked off Dillahunty, who stormed out of the debate calling Wilson a "jackass". Wilson said, "Hope you and your husband have a good day!" referring to Dillahunty's transgender "wife". It was all kind of soap opera-ish.
ReplyDeleteVideo here:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=S8U34ezKvrU
I do think a lot about prudential concerns. Because invective is permitted, of course doesn’t mean it’s always wise or effective. It’s “fun” so like any virtue it’s got temptations on either side.
ReplyDeleteBecause there is an element of it that can be fun or rewarding personally - and using it effectively to put down others can be admired and so gain us a reputation - I suspect that there will usually be more temptation to use it beyond good sense, than the opposite temptation (i.e. to fail to use it when it is needed). And I suspect that at least for the most part, it will only be used wholesomely, not only in the right place and time and degree, but also for the right reason, by someone who has thought out beforehand what kinds of times and situations call for it, and what kinds of use are likely to be beneficial vs. harmful.
Delete