The
supposition that science amounts to theory plus experiment is, Cartwright
observes, widespread among laymen, scientists, and philosophers alike. The mathematically expressible kind of
scientific theory, familiar from modern physics and enshrined in equations like
F = ma, is taken to be the gold standard. From such equations, it is thought, specific observable
consequences are predicted, and the point of experimentation is to test these
predictions. And that’s basically
it. Except, as Cartwright shows, that
isn’t it, not by a long shot. In
addition to theory and experimentation, there are models, narratives, diagrams,
illustrations, concrete applications, and so on. None of these is reducible to theory or
experiment, and neither are they any less essential to the practice and content
of science. And when we take account of
them, both science and the world it describes are seen to be far more
complicated than the common conception of science and its results implies.
Theoretical concepts
Cartwright
begins her analysis by noting that any theory is expressed in concepts, and that science aims for
concepts with content that is both unambiguous
and empirical. As all philosophers of science know, it turns
out to be very difficult to come up with a general account of how this is
achieved. Cartwright summarizes the
familiar difficulties. First of all,
explicit definitions of theoretical terms are obviously of limited help when
the definition is itself couched in yet further theoretical terms. At some point we need to arrive at terms with
clear empirical content. But exactly how
does that work?
Operationalism held that the solution was to define
a theoretical concept in terms of some operation by which the scientist could
measure the empirical phenomenon captured by the concept. But there are several reasons why this won’t
work. For one thing, it entails
reductionist analyses that we can independently know to be false. Cartwright offers the example of behaviorism,
which was an application of operationalism to psychology. The behaviorist would define anger, for example, in terms of the
observable behavior on the basis of which we would attribute anger to
someone.
Note that
the implication of operationalism here is not just that we can know someone is angry by way of
observing his behavior. It is that there
is nothing more to anger than the
behavior. Now, one problem with this
claim is that it simply isn’t true. A
person could be angry without exhibiting the usual behavioral signs of anger,
and could also exhibit those signs without actually being angry. Hence anger is something more than the
behavior. Another problem is that it
turns out even apart from that to be impossible entirely to analyze anger or
any other mental state in entirely behavioral terms. Suppose we say that “John is angry” means
“John is disposed to raise his voice, frown, stomp his feet, etc.” The trouble is that this sentence will be true
only if John does not desire to hide his feelings. But if we add a reference to the absence of
this desire to our definition, we’ve now got a further mentalistic concept –
desire – that needs to be given a behaviorist analysis. And it turns out that to carry out such an
analysis, we need to make reference to yet further
mental states, with those now needing
a behaviorist analysis, and so on ad
infinitum. Hence the operationalist analysis
cannot actually be carried out.
A second
problem with operationalism is that it has the false implication that there
cannot be different empirical tests for the same concept. For again, operationalism holds that there is
nothing more to a concept than the operation by which we test its
application. Hence, if we have two
different tests, we must be dealing with two different concepts. But that’s absurd. Take, for example, the concept of being
round. I can test whether something is
round either by looking at it or by feeling it, and obviously it is one and the
same concept I am applying in both cases.
A third
problem, as Cartwright emphasizes, is that in actual scientific practice it
often takes a lot of hard work and argumentation to show that a certain
empirical test plausibly measures the reality captured by some scientific
concept. That could not be the case if
there were nothing more to the concept than the empirical test. It follows that there is more to theoretical
concepts than what is captured by such tests, in which case operationalism is
false.
Logical empiricism, as Cartwright notes, was another
failed attempt to solve the problem. The
“logical” component of logical empiricism had to do with its application of
modern formal logic to the formulation of scientific theories, e.g. as
axiomatic systems from which theorems could be deduced. The “empiricism” component had to do with the
idea that the claims of a theory could be verified by observation. Here too there are several problems.
For one
thing, exactly what counts as an observation?
Only what can be perceived by the naked eye (or the naked ear, the naked
nose, etc.)? Or do observations made
using instruments count? Furthermore, what
exactly is it that we are observing – mind-independent physical objects, or
sense data? And are all scientific
claims really verifiable in this way in the first place? (See pp. 139-51 of my book Aristotle’s
Revenge: The Metaphysical Foundations of Physical and Biological Science for detailed discussion of the
intractable problems facing verificationism.)
It turns out
that, just as the content of theoretical concepts outstrips what can be
captured in an operational definition, so too, more generally, does it outstrip
what is observable. The content of
concepts is given instead by the axioms of the theory in which they are
embedded. But the problem now, as
Cartwright notes, is that such axioms are never sufficient to determine exactly
what it is in the empirical world a theory is about. Consider, again, the
equation F = ma. Considered just by
itself, it tells us nothing more than that one quantity is equal to the product
of two others. And as Cartwright
observes, this is true not only of the force, mass, and acceleration of a
material object, but also of the area of a rectangle with respect to the length
of its sides. There is nothing in the
equation itself that tells us which
of these is its subject matter. Of
course, we could add further items to our set of axioms, such as Newton’s law
of universal gravitation. But no matter
how many we add, there will always be alternative possible
interpretations.
(This issue
is closely related to the epistemic structural realist thesis that physical
theories reveal to us only the abstract structure of the physical world and not
its intrinsic nature. See chapter 3 of Aristotle’s Revenge for detailed
discussion.)
Of course,
in practice, scientists and the laymen who are familiar with their work don’t worry
about such problems. The reason is that,
for one thing, when encountering an equation like F = ma, most people have at
least in the backs of their minds the ordinary language usage of terms like “force,”
“mass,” and “acceleration,” and thus naturally interpret the variables in light
of them, even if they know that the variables aren’t meant to correspond
exactly to our commonsense notions. For another
thing, they often apply the equation as a tool for carrying out very practical
tasks, such as figuring out the speed of a ball hit by a tennis player (to
borrow an example of Cartwright’s).
But all of
this comes from outside the theory itself,
at least if we take the mathematics alone to be what is essential to theory as
such. Moreover, as Cartwright emphasizes,
this utility of theory in practical applications does not entail that the world
really is exactly the way the abstract theory represents it as being. (She gives the well-known example of
phlogiston theory, which was very useful predictively and technologically
despite the fact that it turns out that there is no such thing as
phlogiston.)
I would
emphasize a further point. It is
commonly assumed that scientific theory gives us a richer and more accurate
representation of the world than common sense does, and indeed ought to replace
the commonsense description of phenomena.
But as Cartwright’s argument indicates, this is the reverse of the
truth. For one thing, scientific theory
in fact cannot even be given a determinate interpretation without some
connection to the ordinary linguistic usage from which its concepts ultimately
derive, and the concrete applications to which theory is put. For another thing, what theory describes are
really only abstract features of the world of common experience rather than that
world in all its rich complexity. That doesn’t
necessarily entail that scientific theory should be given an instrumentalist rather
than realist interpretation. But it does
support the epistemic structural realist view that, while what theory describes
is really there in nature, it is very far from capturing everything that is
there in nature. (See Aristotle’s Revenge for detailed exposition
and defense of this view.)
Beyond theory
Now, because
of the way the actual applications of a theory often unconsciously determine
how we interpret it, we can be blind to how much work is being done by the
application and how little by the theory considered in isolation. In particular, when we consider a theory in
isolation, just in terms of its mathematical formulation, its concepts can seem
very precise. But a concrete application
of the theory may nevertheless involve an interpretation of those concepts that
is not so precise. Yet it may retain its
utility nonetheless, and retain it precisely because the concepts are being
applied in a way that goes beyond the content of the theory itself.
The
consequence of this is that scientists often end up supposing that precision is
possible where really it is not. Or,
because a concept’s application may be susceptible of precision in one, limited
domain, scientists can fallaciously suppose that it must be equally capable of
precision when extended beyond that domain.
This is, Cartwright argues, especially likely in social science. She gives as an example the notion of probability. When we consider simple examples like pulling
cards from a fair deck, the probabilities of various possible outcomes can be
determined with precision. But it simply
doesn’t follow that we can meaningfully assign probabilities to events in
general, and Cartwright thinks there are good reasons to suppose that this is
not in fact possible.
In
particular, she notes that probabilities are determined relative to what Ian
Hacking calls “chance set-ups.” These
are circumstances where both the possible outcomes and the processes that might
lead to them can be fully specified, and where there are probabilities built
into the situation at the start from which the probabilities we wish to
calculate fall out logically. Again,
pulling cards from a fair deck would be an example. But much of what happens in nature does not amount
to a chance set-up in this sense. For
example, in the real world (as opposed to what Cartwright calls the “small
world” representations that social scientists make use of) there often simply isn’t
one relatively simple and fixed set of variables that might influence possible
outcomes.
For this
reason, Cartwright judges that much of what is said by social scientists about “effect
sizes” when evaluating alternative policy proposals is poorly founded. (Cartwright doesn’t mention the relevance of
all this to arguments for various pandemic policies, criminal justice reforms, “equity-conscious”
educational proposals, and other currently trendy issues, but it is
obvious. I leave the specifics as
homework.)
In any
event, in natural science and social science alike, Cartwright argues, theory
is only ever brought to bear on the world by way of various
intermediaries. First of all, there are
the idealized models by which we bring
abstractions like the laws of physics to bear on concrete reality. For example, when we apply Newton’s laws to the
solar system, we do so by modeling the latter (in terms of a system of point
masses orbiting a larger point mass, and so on). In this way, our application of abstractions
is mediated by further abstractions. There
are also the concrete narratives by which
all of these abstractions are made intelligible. (Think of the way that, in order to
understand even a simple system like the solar system, we still have crudely to
visualize large objects moving through space over time around other large
objects; that in order to understand the implications of special relativity, we
tell stories about twins traveling on rocket ships; and so on.) Cartwright notes that diagrams, graphs, and illustrations also deeply influence how
we interpret and apply theory. Nor are these
various intermediaries dispensable. We
simply couldn’t understand or make use of theories without them.
Finally,
experimentation too, Cartwright argues, is a much more complex affair than is
implied by the common notion that “science = theory + experiment.” Experiment is often treated as if its only
point is to test theory. But that is not
the case. Sometimes experimentation is
carried out even in the absence of any well-worked out theory, in an exploratory way that aims simply to see
what will happen under various circumstances.
Sometimes experimentation creates
new phenomena that would otherwise not be observed – where, precisely because they
have not otherwise been observed, no theory yet exists to account for
them. Sometimes experimentation reconstitutes phenomena in the sense of deeply
altering our understanding of them, even in the absence of theoretical
considerations. And in all these cases,
experimentation, like theory, depends on fixing the content of concepts, on
models, and so on.
“Science ain’t an exact science”
I’ve
mentioned already one of the implications I see in Cartwright’s discussion,
viz. support for an epistemic structural realist interpretation of modern
physics. Here’s another. It is a commonplace of modern philosophy of
science that theory is underdetermined
by empirical evidence. What that means
is that for any body of empirical evidence, there are always alternative
possible theories that are incompatible with each other but consistent with
that evidence. That does not entail that all theories are equally
good, but only that considerations independent of both theory and empirical
evidence are ultimately necessary in order to choose between theories. Philosophers of science like Thomas Kuhn and
Paul Feyerabend have also shown how extra-scientific considerations (of a
philosophical sort, for example) play a crucial role in determining the outcome
of scientific investigation.
The
considerations raised by Cartwright greatly reinforce these judgments. In particular, they reinforce the
underdetermination of theory by evidence insofar as it isn’t just alternative
theories that are compatible with the same empirical evidence. There are also the alternative possible
models, narratives, diagrams, etc. which mediate between theory and evidence. And as with theories, so too with models,
narratives, diagrams, etc., philosophical considerations no less than empirical
ones can influence our judgments about what is within the range of respectable
options, what is plausible all things considered, and so forth.
By no means
does this entail that science is not a rational enterprise, any more than
philosophy is not a rational enterprise.
What it does entail, though, is that the
boundary between science and philosophy is much less sharp than is commonly
supposed. As I have argued at length
elsewhere (including in Aristotle’s
Revenge), much of what is today assumed to be “scientific” – the refusal to
countenance irreducibly teleological explanations, the primary/secondary
quality distinction, and so on – are really just contentious philosophical
assumptions masquerading as empirical results.
And it is not possible to do science without making philosophical
assumptions of some kind, which are bound to be controversial.
To borrow a
line from the movie 12 Monkeys, “science
ain’t an exact science.” To be sure, there
is an exactness in its purely mathematical aspects, but that is precisely
because mathematical representations simply leave out all aspects of reality
that don’t fit that exact mode of representation – which turns out to be quite
a lot. There are not only more things in
heaven and earth than are dreamt of by scientists, there is more to science itself than is dreamt of by
them.
Related
reading:
Dupré
on the ideologizing of science
Scientism:
America’s State Religion
From a review of the works of the philosopher of science, Rev. William Wallace, OP, which nicely sums up what Prof. Cartwright is saying.
ReplyDelete"That conviction, that the principles of Aristotle’s logic and natural philosophy, especially as understood by St. Thomas Aquinas, were still the most profound and accurate lens through which to understand the reality of the natural world and the progress of modern science."
WCB
ReplyDeleteScience, as a word can be misleading. It assumes a sort of category that does not really exist. Astronomy, as a science is different from biochemistry chemistry. Biochemistry is different from theoretical physics and particle physics. Geology is different and so is field botany. Each field of studay has its own techniques, equipment and tools, and history. Aristotle's
"Science" has been dead since the days of Galileo. Galileo, a professor of physics threw all of physics out and started investigating physics empiracally, dropping objects, rolling objects down planks etc to found physics on a sound experimental, observational basis.
Optics changed everything. Telescopes and microscopes exposed whole new worlds to observe not found in Bible, Islamic science or Greek philosophers. You cannot outguess nature. And the naked eye is not good enough. This was a major wake up call for everyone.
With the golden age of scientific instruments, science was born as we know it. Natural philosophy was a dead issue.
With Descarte's and friends failure to explain how soul or spirit interacted with matter, theology and science parted ways. The most orthodox Catholic chemist and rank atheist chemist did chemistry the same way post Decartes.
Methodological materialism is the basis of modern science and will ever remain so.
WCB
"If I repeat it enough times, and sprinkle it among some obvious and uncontroversial statements without showing logical connection, it will come true. But I must keep my eyes tightly shut, since I'm posting it underneath a blog full of hundreds of pages of counterargument that I don't want to know about because I'm scared I might be wrong.
Delete"Mouth open, eyes shut; mouth open, eyes shut; mouth open, eyes shut. Hey, it's working!"
WCB
DeleteThe era where some philosopher cogitated mightily and pulled some theory out of his ear has long been over. With the invention of telescopes and microscopes, mankind found out there is a lot of things going on one cannot observe with a naked eye. A very important step in the development of real science. An important step in the development of science was the invention, and devolpment of scientific instruments and techniques to expand our abilities to observe nature.
Science was becoming effective and sophisticated and Aristotle became irrelevant to modern science.
WCB
"...Aristotle became irrelevant to modern science..." Heisenberg (one of the most important founders of modern physics) would not agree.
DeleteThere is a vast literature that proves you wrong on theoretical grounds. But since your assertion "answers" the arguments in the article with this historical "analysis", i will limit myself at these statements.
Delete" Galileo, a professor of physics threw all of physics out and started investigating physics empiracally"
"The era where some philosopher cogitated mightily and pulled some theory out of his ear has long been over. "
You can believe this ready-made positivist version of it. Or you can try to read the work of a great historian of science like Alexadre Koyré beginning with the article "Galileo and Plato"
https://www.jstor.org/stable/2707166
and see that the process was much more complex and indeed has required philosophical thinking and not in a secondary position. Point is your "analysis" is wrong on theretical grounds also because it is historically wrong.
WCB
DeleteHistorically, inventions like telescopes and microscopes changed everything.
That is history. You cannot outguess nature without such tools. This was indeed the sobering realization that change atitudes of how to do science.
Aristotle, plato and pre-telescope and pre-micrscope thinkers had no chance of understaning much of anything worth mentioning. Drivers of science were no longer philosophers, but instrument makers. Better telescopes, microscopes and instruments to observe nature one could not do with the naked eye.
There is no other way to do effective and meaningful science.
WCB
You simply don't know what are you talking about and present, i repeat myself, a crude positivistic sketch that is as simplistic as, as a consequence, factually wrong. Instruments are important but without philosophical ideas to guide their use (such as the platonic understanding of the role of mathematics in the study of nature), those instruments (and not all of them, because other important instruments came to be as a conseguence of this process) would have no use whatsoever in the formation of different paradigms, but just pratical uses, like many exemples in history.
DeleteThe tools need an idea to change things; if you really studied history and good philosophy of science (quite rare these days) you would know that various tools, necessary for various "scientific discoveries" were already present in various places and times, like in ancient China or in the hellenistic period, but what was lacking the kind of ideas, philosophical ones to be clear, that could change the paradygm; and the social form to accept/incourage it, in this case the various elements (socio-economical, ideological and, of course, also technical) involved in the process of formation of "modern age" and, indeed, of capitalism.
The role itself that technological craft came to to have in the research is a consequence of philosophical positions (Bacon, Descartes, etc.), as you can see with the image universe-machine and God-clockmaker. It is a philosophical metaphor and the shift was prepared by an interation of philosophical speculations, socio-economical changes and processes that included the technological development, when the speculation integrated it in a theoretical vision (that, of course was fueled also by economic and military interests).
A telescope without Galilei platonic understanding of nature would have been useful only to see better the enemy deck during a naval fight.
All this said in a neutral way, just looking at the process and not judging it, because phenomenological understanding of a process is one thing, judgment of the phenomenon is another.
Now it would be auspicable that you read the damn article of Koyré (and really you should at least read "From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe" by him), not to say other works of good literature on the matter, just to begin (for instance the various studies on how Newton's metaphysics was necessary for his physics), and come with an actual proposition that answers those arguments, you know dialectics, instead of reiterating your positivistic tell-tale.
WCB
DeleteThere were other things going on in Enlightenment Europe. Rediscovery of the Greek Skeptics. Printing of Lucretius's Epicurean writings. Pierre Bayle's Philosophical Encyclopedia. And more.the European progress at better and better scientific instruments was a big reason why Europe leaped to the forefront of science in the world. Scholasticism, empty philosophisizing were no longer adequate. Scientific Europeans discove Dr ed what Richard Feynman called " The joy of finding things out". Scientific societies made science a status symbol that rewarded the best and brightest.
WCB
Really, i can't bother. What could follow would be ad hominem, because, simply, you live in your semi-accultured bubble and understand very little of these subjects, but you think you know because you share a very ideological mockery of them. There is nothing to answer; "better", "best and brightest", it's fantasy, bad fantasy, i like good one, there is no rational basis to continue, even in dialectical disagreement. I just give dr. Feser my apologies because i wanted to contribute to a discussion no to do a polemic.
DeleteAlam,
DeleteDon't bother. WCB is a lazy troll who doesn't care about arguments or discussion. He just proselytize like a good hard naturalist/new atheist/scientistic type. And, of course, he won't listen, nor even realize he has no arguments to support his positions.
What's more is that he doesn't even care to make an account, so everyone can impersonate him. I suspect he's nothing more than a sockpuppet of the usual atheistrolls.
The theories of the hard sciences are indeed accurate in quantitive abstraction of quantity, but lack sufficient ontological depth to be able to confirm their correlation with truth. I don’t think the social sciences are accurate in either aspects!
ReplyDeleteWCB
DeleteWith a multi-billion dolar CERN particle accerator, one can confirm the existence of the Higgs particle and Higgs field. Explaining the deep processes of particle physics.
All the thick philosophical and theological tomes on ontology (of which there are many) will add nothing
To the understanding of the Higs particle or basic physics.
It neither leads there, predicts anything, helps design the upgraded design that found the Higgs particle. For that one is better off learning tensor calculus.
WCB
WCB
DeleteMichael Faraday's theories on electro-magnetical physics are true. His field equations are true. Objectively true. They are the basis of our modern world and its reliance on elctricity, and electrical devices. None of this needs philosophers' opinions about ontology.
One good experiment is worth a thousand opinions.
WCB
Technologically the basis of the modern world is quantum physics not classical physics. And quantum physics and Aristotle go together like peas and carrots.
DeleteSo, it is confirmed, your understanding of science is as crude of your understanding of philosophy and history, if you think that crude mockery of it you exposed above is history. Perhaps you should do a research about the meaning of the concept "truth" to understand that no experiment is "true". That you think that "scientific certainty" is truth tell much about your understanding of such matters.
DeleteAnd a study about the nature and history of mathematical models woul be in order. I'm sorry, can't help here, my bibliography on this is in italian.
Ah, i may have double-posted above, i don't know, can't see my comments until approval. Sorry.
WCB
Delete"It doesn't matter how beautiful your theory is, it doesn't matter how smart you are. If it doesn't agree with experiment, it's wrong."
- Richard P. Feynman
Shut up and experiment, is what is the basic process of science. It is sobering to read the history of modern physics and see how much of what we now know was discovered by physicists messing around in a lab somewhere. Utter surprizes. Basic ideas like Plato's Forms and Aristotle's Categories have not stood the test of time as fruitful ideas.
WCB
@WCB Richard Feynman was a psychopath.
DeleteSure, physicists experimenting has taught us a great deal about physics. But physics doesn’t explain all of reality. Not even close.
DeleteAs i said, you don't even know what the basis of science are, starting with the role of interpretation in it (and this just for starters), the required gnoseology, epistemology and other wee philosophical things. What you "know" is just the positivist popularizer version of it. "It is sobering", indeed, because it is exacltly what it is that you are doing, cradling your little self in a ideology; and you dare speak about religion and philosophy. Rationality, indeed. I won't further reply to you, it would be pretty irrational.
DeleteProfessor Feser, would it be a fair representation of the thomistic understanding of laws of nature as merely a description of how the universe acts without the interference of an outside agent?
ReplyDeleteI am reminded of a philosopher who once gave this description, it may have been JL Mackie but I cannot be sure.
WCB
DeleteWili!m of Ockham. God created nature, the material world and the laws of nature. Known as seconday causes. Once set in motion, God does not cause everything to happen by direct action. An idea that continued on with the philosophy of Descartes. God the great clock maker. Nature as a secondary cause is an old concept with venerable theological roots.
WCB
i would argue that Ockham and Descartes were both an axe at the root of theology, although of course that was not the intention of either. The older understanding could still be seen as having a distinction between primary and secondary causes. However with the rediscovery of Aristotle in the west, the basis of the christian neoplatonic foundation of the past thousand years was slowly lost. In this the primary cause was naturally the divine idea(l)s of things, the eternal form towards which things unfolded in time. This was the basis of teleology which became uprooted after Oakham and even more so after the cartesian divide, where laws of nature (secondary causes) start to be seen as a kind of primary magic that acts on our abstraction of reality. As if reality is our abstraction of it.
Delete@Simon Adams here is what Jesus said about Aristotle:
Delete"So again Jesus said to them, 'Very truly, I tell you, I am the gate for the sheep. All who came before me are thieves and bandits.'" (John 10:7-8)
Every great world teacher that came before Jesus (Hillel, Shammai, Aristotle, Socrates, the Buddha, Zoroaster, etc...) was from the Evil One. William of Occam and Descartes were doing the greater works of Jesus Christ by destroying Aristotle. "For this purpose the Son of God was manifested, that He might destroy the works of the devil." (1 John 3:8)
@infinite growth. I don’t know where to start in replying to that. Ockham was paying TOO MUCH attention to Aristotle. There is a reason (in my view) that the Church Fathers chose to focus more on the neoplatonic ontology than on Aristotle. The essences are ‘essentially’ missing in Aristotle, but not in Augustine or Aquinas.
DeleteFor you to think that Ockham, whose primary aim was to find certainty, was working with Christ, whilst the Church fathers like Augustine, whose primary aim was Christ, were against Him, seems very upside down.
@Simon Adams Jesus is saying that all knowledge that came before Him was false. Whether it be Judaism, Buddhism, Greek philosophy, etc.... But He didn't say that all knowledge that comes after Him will be false. And indeed, knowledge didn't explode until after the Protestant reformation when the "ancient wisdom" was thrown out and science was embraced. Even though Muhammad, Karl Marx, and Alfred Kinsey are seen as the unholy trinity of traditional Catholics, the truth is, Jesus didn't call them bandits, because they came after Him.
Delete"Ancient wisdom" comes from the Evil One. Jesus Himself said so in John's gospel. That makes me question many "traditional" "time-honored" interpretations of the New Testament. Especially the seemingly irrational idea that behaviors between consenting adults (same-sex relationships) somehow can make the Creator of a spatially infinite universe angry.
@InfiniteGrowth You seem to have a very strange, possibly fringe protestant, understanding. Both Paul and John referenced Greek philosophy. If you’re Christian then this is holy spirit inspired scripture. So the black and white interpretation you have of Jesus words contradicts the very “sola scriptura” framework you seem to be using.
DeleteOf course not all of all ancient beliefs are compatible with what was revealed by Jesus, which is why the Christian neoplatonism of the “1000 years” of Christianity up to the errors of nominalism and the reformation was not the same as the non christian neoplatonism.
WCB
Delete@Simon Adams
"I would argue that Ockham and Descartes were both an axe at the root of theology, although of course that was not the intention of either."
Aristotle states the Unmoved Mover, Aristotle's God, set the Universe into motion and then withdrew from the material world, contemplating his own thouhts. Aristotle tells us that is the highest form of existence for this Unmoved Mover.
Thus nature is for Aristotle, a secondary cause, and neatly avoids the issue of the problem of evil.
Othodox Christianity early on adopted the ides of God's omnipresence, immanence and providence. Reaching its ultimate conclusion with Calvanism.
WCB
Calvinism is not the ultimate conclusion of anything, just another branch of the ever fissile protestantism….!
DeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
Delete@InfiniteGrowth: I’m afraid as someone who was once an atheist, none of these 16th century religions make any sense to me. Why would God become incarnate at a particular point in space and time, an incarnation tied deeply to the creation of the universe at the beginning of time, and then leave behind apostles who basically failed? The real presence was the natural understanding of the eucharist from the start, it’s the reality experienced by the greatest saints of Christianity, how did Calvin suddenly get a better understanding all those years later? How do any protestants know that Matthew, Mark, Luke and John are the gospels that are the source of truth, and not the gospel of Judas, the acts of Peter etc?
DeleteI understand that by the 15th century the Catholic church was very powerful, and so sometimes attracted some ‘worldly’ people who abused that power. However this is true of all human organisations over even far shorter periods of time. Like war, it’s a human problem rather than a religion problem.
I certainly don’t see any need for Calvinism or any protestant theology now. Our understanding is always going to be at least partially apophatic, but the Catholic church has centuries of pondering all that was passed down to us, and all that has been revealed since. It has been given the power to forgive sins through apostolic succession. Anyone can sit before the real presence in any catholic church. These are realities that you can experience, outward signs of inward graces. Why would anyone go anywhere else?
A very insightful post! Loved it!
ReplyDeleteFrom an epistemological point of view, discussing science would be less controversial if we simply acknowledged and agreed that:
ReplyDelete(1) Certainty (i.e., the judgement of "truth" when comparing what we know with our experiences) is limited to our own personal experiences and cannot be shared with others by definition.
(2) Objectivity (i.e., putting ourselves in the place of the object or pretending to represent its perspective) is an extrapolation that cannot be verified.
(3) Objectivity as impartiality is a matter of consensus among certainties communicated through language and agreement on a narrative.
(4) Mathematics is a human invention in the sense that its rules do not exist a priori in a realm of ideas. It is incorrect to imagine the object of mathematics as something to explore like an unknown land, but it is more akin to something we build like a Lego game. It is also a narrative, where formulas and diagrams are similar to Chinese ideograms in that they can be read and understood within their own cultural frames.
(5) Physics is a narrative, and the evaluation of its quality does not rely on its ability to predict, but on its ability to function as a useful and operational story, depending on the culture in which it is developed. There is no pretension of certainty or objectivity, only impartiality.
(6) Metaphysics is the only narrative that claims to develop a narrative that examines certainty and objectivity as defined above.
(7) What is common to all these narratives, what underlies them all, is logic, and for obvious reasons, the logic that is supported by our own certain experiences, as declined by Aristotle.
Modern physics is quantum mechanical. The founders of modern physics (Heisenberg, Bohr, Born etc...) understood that the ontology behind classical physics had been proven wrong by experimental results that could only be explained through quantum mechanics. Heisenberg understood that physicists must now resign themselves (see below). This means that physics is no longer ontological at all but now presupposes existence (this was always the case but classical, Newtonian physics made it easy to neglect this fact). If you want ontology you have to go to philosophy which inevitably leads to theology (see Przywara "Analogia Entis").
ReplyDelete“...The atomic physicist has had to resign himself to the fact that his science is but a link in the infinite chain of man's argument with nature, and that it cannot simply speak of nature "in itself". Science always presupposes the existence of man and, as Bohr has said, we must become conscious of the fact that we are not merely observers but also actors on the stage of life…”
Werner Heisenberg, The Physicist’s Conception of Nature (London, 1958)
The true reason why communism doesn't work is because you can't legislate people to have empathy. The Soviet Union taught that by abolishing religion and instilling scientific values in education that they could create an empathetic citizenry and it failed miserably.
ReplyDeleteRight-wing economic theories (e.g. von Mises, Hayek, Rand, etc…) are all based on the axiom that empathy is not necessary to build a sustainable society: that everyone could be a complete psychopath but as long as they're aware of their desires, can perform calculation and comparison and perform human action a flourishing society can be built. This is madness. In objective reality, empathy is the necessary and sufficient logical condition for building a sustainable society.
DeleteThe conservative "twist" on right-wing economics that controlling external behavior (e.g. banning drugs, pornography, enforcing morality, etc...) can make up for an economic system without empathy is ludicrous.
People call communists atheists, but in objective reality right-wing economics is far more atheistic, because it presupposes that empathy is a mistake and it exists for no reason. That people feel empathy is based on an "accident" and has nothing to do with the ultimate nature of reality.
WCB
DeleteIf we read Acts 4, it would seem God commands Christian communism.
WCB
@WCB The people in Acts 4 were all empowered by the Holy Spirit and had empathy, so communism worked. It cannot work for the world at large though unless you subscribe to postmillennialism (the official position of the Holy Catholic Church is amillennialism).
DeleteWCB
DeleteOne would have thought God would have sent the Holy Ghost to Marx, Engles, Lenin and Stalin and gave them the Word of God as to do this Communism thing..
As it was. It was one of humanity's great social experiments. 70 years of Communism, 70 years of utter failure. Experiment over. Other grand ideas that failed, wide spread chattel slavery, feudalism, Facism, and neo-Liberalism.
Fools never learn from their mistakes. Smart men learn from their mistakes. Wise men learn from the mistakes of others. That is why wise men study history.
WCB
WCB
Delete"This is why wise men study history."
Wow! Such a simple and obvious statement, yet so utterly profound. That IS wisdom. Please continue.
WCB
DeleteAnd often people don't bother to study history with understanding. For example Vladamir Putin.
WCB
@Other anonymous
DeleteIs it me or is WCB blissfully unaware he's being trolled at? :D
WCB
DeleteScience today is based on methodological materialism, experimentation, and continuing development of technology to enable better observation of the Universe.
All we need to know.
Can anyone tell us anything since the days of Galileo where metaphysicians beat the empirical scientist to any major discovery?
Sute, some scientists have dabbled in metaphysical speculation, but in the end it was careful observation and experimentaion that provided scientific progress.
Sometimes to great distress to some as cherished ideas were disproven.
Trolled? Not very well.
WCB
@wcb Science, by its very nature, is concerned with understanding the underlying principles of the natural world. This requires a belief in the existence of an objective reality that is separate from our subjective perceptions. Without this belief, it would be impossible to develop the scientific method, which is based on the idea that the natural world is knowable and that knowledge can be acquired through observation and experimentation.
DeleteYou also need some kind of framework for understanding the relationship between the natural world and our concepts of it. How is the natural world knowable? Materialism has cut off the abstraction of quantities from what is abstracted and how it’s abstracted, and then ignored this as if it’s irrelevant magic that just happens in the background. Yes this process is very effective at developing theories of what is presented to us as reality. However to then claim that the quantitive abstraction IS reality is like looking at a great painting under the microscope, and claiming that the painting is nothing more than pigment on canvas fibres. It’s only correct if you restrict reality in a very warped way.
WCB
DeleteOne can either try to work from metaphysics to physics, or from physics to metaphysics. From metaphysics to physics does not work. The development of Relativity and Quantum physics put an end to that. The real Universe is far to weird to do that. Only experimentation that demonstrates how weird real physics is is truly meanigful.
Gravity is a prime example. Modern physics cannot understand gravity as it relates to quantum mechanics. And no metaphysics helps to solve the problem. Not hylomorphism, or forms or Pythagorean mathematical.metaphysics.
WCB
WCB
I have a question. Can you make an argument for immateriality of the soul from meaning/intentionality eve though you committed to the aristotelian world view picture? In other words, can argument like this: (Your thoughts has a meaning but everything material is meaningless, therefore your thoughts are immaterial.) work for one that is holding aristotelian world view picture?
ReplyDeleteWho says that everything material is meaningless? That's just begging the question.
DeleteDoll
DeleteMaybe Dr Feser will answer that question in his forthcoming book on the. soul.
WCB
DeleteA nice cherry pie is material, but hardly meaningless. One cannot eat metaphysics.
WCB
That is in fact that main Thomistic-Aristotelian argument for the immateriality of the rational human soul.
DeleteSpecifically, by virtue of being rational, our intellects are capable of grasping universals with our thoughts, and universals are necessarily eternal and immaterial, transcending any temporal material thing, hence there must be an immaterial and eternal component to our rational intellects.
And that means that the substantial forms (aka the souls) of rational creatures are forms of immaterial and eternal substances, albeit substances with material components that are naturally essential to them but are lost at death. And that in turn fits in nicely with the Christian doctrine of the resurrection of the body.
So the Aristotelian picture is not only compatible with the the immortality of the soul, it has traditionally been seen by Christians as presaging and being completed by the Christian understanding of the bodily resurrection of the dead.
The Professor has already dealt with this in his book "Philosophy of Mind", which I would recommend. He also demonstrates how any meaning that material things have is dependent on mind for its significance.
ReplyDeleteEd:
ReplyDelete"For example, when we apply Newton’s laws to the solar system, we do so by modeling the latter (in terms of a system of point masses orbiting a larger point mass, and so on). In this way, our application of abstractions is mediated by further abstractions."
It occurs to me that fact is itself presents a pretty solid argument that hylomorphism or something like it must be true.
If material objects did not have form as per hylomorphism, we would have a vicious infinite regress of mediating abstractions, with no way of "connecting" the mathematical representation to the things being represented. It is only because material objects do have that abstract component - the forms that they instantiate - that mathematical equations and other abstractions can be meaningfully applied to them at all.
But at the same time, if material objects were pure abstraction, there would be no such need to mediate between the abstract model and the concrete material thing, because there would BE no concrete material thing. There would only be the abstraction itself, and the hence the "right" equations would simply be identical to the material objects rather than modeling them.
So the very act of mathematical modeling implicitly requires that all material things are composites of matter and form as per hylomorphic dualism.
You may be interested in this
DeleteScott Berman:
Platonism and the Objects of Science
https://www.amazon.com/Platonism-Objects-Science-Scott-Berman/dp/1350080217
I find it always mysterious when people attempt to demonstrate the truth or falsity of hylomorphism through physical experiences. It's as if they believe that the form of a chair or a dog can be found experimentally within its physical elements, proving its existence. This reminds me of Descartes, who had a lack of understanding of scholastic concepts and believed that the human soul, or human form, could be located in the pineal gland. It's a mystery of the blogosphere's culture.
ReplyDeleteWCB
DeleteYes, the pineal gland nonsense was silly. An old idea from Galen. It solved nothing so a lot of otherwise smart people spent years trying to figure out occasionalism. In the end the entire enterprise of trying to demonstrate how the soul or spirit interacted with matter died a natural death. Hylomorphism did not step in to save the day. Plato's forms did not. Nor vitalism.
Soul or spirit and matter no longer are part of modern science. Methodological naturalism, physicalism has stood the test of time.
WCB
WCB. I truly do not understand what you are talking about: my bad most probably. It could be useful for you in order to communicate fruitfully that you define precisely the terms you use: as physicist and philosopher I do not have any cue. Thank you
DeleteIt depends, I'd say. In general, following William Jaworski, hylomorphism can be argued for in the fields where reduction is impossible, and this can be found within physics as well.
DeleteBut yes, due to the nature of empirical sciences, there's no way to experimentally confirm any metaphysical hypothesis
@Dominik A form refers to the "whatness" of an object, meaning its essential characteristic or defining feature that gives it its specific nature or identity. This "whatness" can only be known by a cognitive agent and is present in both material and immaterial entities. It cannot be object of experience, as an instrument of measure is not a cognitive agent as such (but our five senses, obviously).
DeleteFeser writes: "That does not entail that all theories are equally good, but only that considerations independent of both theory and empirical evidence are ultimately necessary in order to choose between theories. Philosophers of science like Thomas Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend have also shown how extra-scientific considerations (of a philosophical sort, for example) play a crucial role in determining the outcome of scientific investigation." -- So implied here: scientific considerations are dependent on theory and/or empirical evidence, whereas extra-scientific considerations are not? I wonder, how does one show that such extra-scientific considerations (of a philosophical sort, for example) are indeed extra-scientific?
ReplyDelete