Mathematics is
an iceberg on which the Titanic of modern empiricism founders. It is good now and then to remind ourselves
why, and Gottlob Frege’s famous critique of John Stuart Mill in The
Foundations of Arithmetic is a useful starting point. Whether Frege is entirely fair to Mill is a
matter of debate. Still, the fallacies
he attributes to Mill are often committed by others. For example, occasionally a student will
suggest that the proposition that 2 + 2 = 4 is really just a generalization
from our experience of finding four things present after we put one pair next
to another – and that if somehow a fifth thing regularly appeared whenever we
did so, then 2 and 2 would make 5.
"One of the best contemporary writers on philosophy" National Review
"A terrific writer" Damian Thompson, Daily Telegraph
"Feser... has the rare and enviable gift of making philosophical argument compulsively readable" Sir Anthony Kenny, Times Literary Supplement
Selected for the First Things list of the 50 Best Blogs of 2010 (November 19, 2010)
Friday, June 28, 2019
Tuesday, June 25, 2019
Just say the damn sentence already
Suppose you
are a Catholic who thinks the death penalty ought never to be applied in practice under modern
circumstances. Fine. You’re within your rights. Whatever one thinks of the arguments for that
position, it is certainly orthodox. However,
that position is very different from saying that capital punishment is always and intrinsically wrong, wrong per se or of its very nature. That position
is not orthodox. It is manifestly contrary to scripture, the
Fathers and Doctors of the Church, and the consistent teaching of the popes up
until at least Benedict XVI. The
evidence for this claim is overwhelming, and I have set it out in many places –
for example, in this
article and in this
book co-written with Joe Bessette.
Attempts to refute our work have invariably boiled down to ad hominem attacks, red herrings,
question-begging assertions, special pleading, straw man fallacies, or other
sophistries and time-wasters.
Wednesday, June 19, 2019
Links for thinkers
David
Oderberg’s article “Death,
Unity, and the Brain” appears in Theoretical
Medicine and Bioethics.
Nicholas
Maxwell at Aeon calls
for a revival natural philosophy.
Gee, maybe someone ought to write a
book on the subject.
Philosopher
Kathleen Stock on gender
dysphoria and the reality of sex differences, at Quillette. At Medium, philosopher Sophie Allen asks: If
transwomen are women, what is a woman?
The Onion on liberal
self-satisfaction.
Saturday, June 15, 2019
The bishops and capital punishment
A group of
five prelates comprising Cardinal Raymond Burke, Bishop Athanasius Schneider,
Cardinal Janis Pujats, Archbishop Tomash Peta, and Archbishop Jan Pawel Lenga this
week issued a “Declaration of the truths relating to some of the
most common errors in the life of the Church of our time.” Among the many perennial Catholic doctrines that
are now commonly challenged but are reaffirmed
in the document is the following:
In accordance with Holy Scripture and
the constant tradition of the ordinary and universal Magisterium, the Church
did not err in teaching that the civil power may lawfully exercise capital
punishment on malefactors where this is truly necessary to preserve the
existence or just order of societies (see Gen 9:6; John 19:11; Rom 13:1-7;
Innocent III, Professio
fidei Waldensibus praescripta; Roman
Catechism of the Council of Trent, p.
III, 5, n. 4; Pius XII, Address to Catholic jurists on December 5, 1954).
Tuesday, June 11, 2019
Augustine on capital punishment
In his book On
Augustine: The Two Cities, Alan Ryan says that Augustine’s
“understanding of the purpose of punishment made the death penalty simply
wrong” (p. 82). That is a bit of an
overstatement. In The City of God, Augustine writes:
However, there are some exceptions
made by the divine authority to its own law, that men may not be put to
death. These exceptions are of two
kinds, being justified either by a general law, or by a special commission
granted for a time to some individual. And
in this latter case, he to whom authority is delegated, and who is but the
sword in the hand of him who uses it, is not himself responsible for the death
he deals. And, accordingly, they who
have waged war in obedience to the divine command, or in
conformity with His laws, have represented in their persons the
public justice or the wisdom of government, and in this capacity have put
to death wicked men; such persons have by no means violated
the commandment, “You shall not kill.” (Book I, Chapter 21)
Friday, June 7, 2019
A clarification on integralism
Talk of
integralism is all the rage in recent weeks, given the dispute between David
French and Sohrab Ahmari and Matthew Continetti’s analysis of the state of
contemporary conservatism, on which I commented in a
recent post. What is
integralism? Rod Dreher quotes
the following definition from the blog The Josias:
Catholic Integralism is a tradition
of thought that rejects the liberal separation of politics from concern with
the end of human life, holding that political rule must order man to his final
goal. Since, however, man has both a temporal and an eternal end, integralism
holds that there are two powers that rule him: a temporal power and a spiritual
power. And since man’s temporal end is subordinated to his eternal end the
temporal power must be subordinated to the spiritual power.
Sunday, June 2, 2019
Continetti on post-liberal conservatism
At the Washington Free Beacon, Matthew
Continetti proposes
a taxonomy of contemporary American conservatism. Among the groups he identifies are the “post-liberals.” What he means by liberalism is not twentieth-
and twenty-first century Democratic Party liberalism, but rather the broader
liberal political and philosophical tradition that extends back to Locke,
informed the American founding, and was incorporated into the “fusionist”
program of Buckley/Reagan-style conservatism.
The “post-liberals” are conservatives who think that this broader
liberal tradition has become irredeemably corrupt and maybe always has been,
and thus judge that the fusionist project of marrying a traditionalist view of
morality, family, and religion to the liberal political tradition is incoherent
and ought to be abandoned.