Tuesday, January 27, 2015

What’s the deal with sex? Part I


In the second edition of his book Practical Ethics, Peter Singer writes:

[T]he first thing to say about ethics is that it is not a set of prohibitions particularly concerned with sex.  Even in the era of AIDS, sex raises no unique moral issues at all.  Decisions about sex may involve considerations of honesty, concern for others, prudence, and so on, but there is nothing special about sex in this respect, for the same could be said of decisions about driving a car. (p. 2, emphasis added)

I have long regarded this as one of the most imbecilic things any philosopher has ever said.  That sex has special moral significance, indeed tremendous moral significance, is blindingly obvious.  That is why all of the world religions, and major thinkers from Plato to Augustine to Aquinas to Kant to Freud, have regarded sex as having tremendous moral significance.  Nor do you have to agree with the specific teachings of any of these religions or thinkers to see that it has tremendous moral significance.  Indeed, you don’t necessarily have to take any particular stand on any of the usual “hot button” issues -- abortion, extramarital sex, homosexuality, contraception, etc. -- to see that it has special significance.  What takes real effort is getting yourself not to see the unique significance of sex.  That takes ideological thinking, intellectual dishonesty and slovenliness, or just plain moral obtuseness -- or all of the above, as in the case of “ethicists” like Singer.

There are at least three respects in which sex has special moral significance, and manifestly so:

1. Sex is the means by which new people are made.  Now, how we treat people, especially in matters of life and death, obviously has moral significance.  Indeed, ethics is largely (even if not entirely) concerned with how we treat other people.  So, since sex is the way new people come into being in the first place, it obviously has special moral significance.  Moreover, no one denies that we have special moral responsibilities toward our immediate family members, and especially children.  But the new people who we bring about through sex are, of course, precisely our children.  Hence sex is very morally significant indeed.

Of course, some people deny that new people are directly brought into being by sex.  For example, defenders of abortion often claim that embryos and even fetuses are not really persons but only “potential persons.”  Naturally, I disagree with this.  Embryos and fetuses are not “potential persons”; rather they are persons, but persons who have not yet realized certain of their key potentials.  But for present purposes this is not a debate that needs to be resolved.  Even people who make claims of the sort in question admit that abortion raises serious moral issues that the defender of abortion has to deal with.  For even they would at least allow that embryos and fetuses are “potential persons” in a way that other things are not “potential persons,” insofar as they have a natural tendency to become persons that other things (an unfertilized ovum, a dog, etc.) do not have.  But the way these “potential persons” typically come into being is, of course, through sex.  Hence sex has at the very least a unique indirect connection to the generation of new persons.  Thus if aborting so-called “potential persons” raises serious moral questions, it follows that sex raises serious moral questions. 

To be sure, defenders of abortion take different views about how serious the moral questions raised by abortion are.  Some admit that abortion is at least regrettable and better avoided all things being equal, even if they think it ought to be permitted.  They maintain that abortion should be “safe, legal, and rare.”  Others don’t particularly care whether it’s rare.  But even they typically admit that it takes a fair amount of argumentation to show that this attitude is morally legitimate.  Hence even Singer -- who explains that his book “contains no discussion of sexual morality” because he thinks sex lacks any special moral significance -- devotes an entire chapter to the subject of abortion.  Now if it weren’t for sex, there would of course be no abortion issue in the first place.  Hence if even Singer admits that abortion raises morally significant questions, he should also admit that sex has special moral significance.  After all, the reason for most abortions is precisely to avoid having to take the special moral responsibility for a new human being that letting the child be born would entail.  Even the abortion defender should admit that any behavior that puts you in the situation of having either to get an abortion or take special moral responsibility for some new human being is itself a pretty morally significant kind of behavior.

Note that it is not a good objection to point out that much sexual behavior does not actually result in new people, and that new people might come about in other ways (artificial insemination and cloning).  Obviously, sex and the production of new people are nevertheless connected in a special way.  For one thing, the biological function of sex is to make new people, even if it doesn’t always in fact result in new people.  Sex only exists in the first place because it has this reproductive function.  (This is so even given a reductionist naturalistic analysis of biological function rather than a non-reductionist Aristotelian analysis; and it is so whether or not one thinks biological function has all the specific moral implications we traditional natural law theorists claim it does.)  For another thing, the other ways in which new people might come about are either relatively rare (only a small percentage of pregnancies are the result of artificial insemination) or still theoretical (cloning), and they are in any event parasitic on the usual way new people come into being, viz. sexual intercourse.  It is only because people already generally reproduce by means of sex that there are natural processes which we might interfere with and thereby cause people to come into being in these other, idiosyncratic ways. 

Consider the following analogy.  I think it’s safe to suppose that most people who would take Singer’s attitude toward sex would also say that guns raise special moral questions that other human artifacts do not, because of the special dangers they pose to human life.  And they would say this despite the fact that most gun use does not result in death, and most deaths do not result from the use of guns.  For guns nevertheless have a propensity for causing death that entails that we ought to be very cautious in using them, and that raises special moral and legal questions.  (Note that it raises these questions however we end up answering them.  The point does not depend on whether one takes a liberal or a conservative view on questions about gun control.)  By the same token, sex obviously has a propensity for causing new people to exist that suffices to give it special moral significance, even if not all sexual intercourse results in new people and even if not all new people result from sexual intercourse. 

2. Sex is the means by which we are completed qua men and women.  Needless to say, a person’s sexual organs require those of another human being of the opposite sex if they are to fulfill their biological function.  In that sense we are incomplete without sex.  But it’s more than just plumbing or physiology.  Most people, for at least a significant portion of their lives, will feel frustrated and unfulfilled if they are unable to have the sort of romantic relationship with another person which has sex as its natural concomitant.  As I argued on natural law grounds in an earlier post, our psychology, no less than our physiology, is naturally “directed toward” another human being as the end required for its completion.  As I also there argued, this sexual psychology forms a continuum, from (to borrow some terminology from C. S. Lewis) mere Venus or basic sexual desire at one end to Eros or full-on romantic longing at the other. 

Of course, there are exceptions.  There are people who forsake such relationships because they are called to a higher state of the sort represented by the priesthood or religious life.  Precisely because the good is a higher good, the person so called is able to overcome the frustration that might otherwise attend such forsaking.  There are also some people who simply lack any significant sexual or romantic desires in the first place.  But in the typical case, human beings will be frustrated by the lack of a sexual relationship with another human being.

Now of course, we traditional natural law types maintain that such a relationship ought to exist only in the context of marriage, and also (as discussed in another earlier post) that the natural end toward which human sexual psychology is directed is a human being of the opposite sex, rather than merely “a person” in the abstract.  But once again, for present purposes, you needn’t agree with all that.  The book of Genesis characterizes our sexual incompleteness in decidedly heterosexual terms.  The myth of Aristophanes in Plato’s Symposium famously portrays it in a much more freewheeling way.  But both testify to the antiquity of the idea that a human being needs another human being sexually for his or her completion.  Advocates of “same-sex marriage” testify to this need as well to the extent that they defend “same-sex marriage” in the name of romantic love and personal fulfillment. 

Failure to succeed in romantic relationships can be not only frustrating in itself, but can affect a person’s sense of self-worth, as can any indication that one simply lacks the capacity to attract or satisfy a lover.  Thus, to belittle a person’s romantic feelings or sexual advances, or to disparage his or her sexual performance or attractiveness to the opposite sex, are all actions considered especially cruel and humiliating.  The presence of a sexual aspect to other harms and misfortunes also makes them much harder to bear.  Adultery is considered a far deeper betrayal than any mere breach of contract.  Rape and child molestation are far more cruel and psychologically scarring than a non-sexual assault.  Exposure of one’s private sexual foibles is regarded as far more humiliating than the disclosure of financial improprieties or other crimes. 

Now, that people take there to be a great deal at stake where sex is concerned -- that they regard success in sexual matters as so important to their happiness, and misfortune in sexual matters as a source of such misery -- makes it simply ludicrous to suggest, as Singer does, that “sex raises no unique moral issues at all” or that “there is nothing special about sex” vis-à-vis the moral considerations relevant to it.  Given the importance people naturally attach to it, they can obviously do serious harm to themselves or to others depending on how they behave sexually.  You might as well say that there is nothing especially morally significant about being a parent, or about being extremely rich, or about being a policeman or a public official. 

It is fatuous to pretend that the moral considerations are entirely extrinsic to sex -- mere “considerations of honesty, concern for others, prudence, and so on… [which apply also to] decisions about driving a car,” as Singer claims.  You could equally well say this of matters Singer thinks do have special moral significance.  For example, you could with no less plausibility say about the distribution of wealth or the state of the environment that they “raise no unique moral issues at all” and that “there is nothing special about” them, but that they merely involve attention to “considerations of honesty, concern for others, prudence, and so on… [which apply also to] decisions about driving a car.”  Yet Singer devotes to each of these topics a chapter in Practical Ethics, and has devoted much attention to them elsewhere as well. 

3. Sex is that area of human life in which the animal side of our nature most relentlessly fights against the rational side of our nature.  Sexual pleasure is the most intense of pleasures.  The reasons for this have to do with the considerations raised in the first two points.  Sex is necessary for the generation of new human beings, but generating new human beings imposes on us enormous costs and responsibilities which we are very reluctant to take on.  Nature has thus made sex so extremely pleasurable that people will engage in it anyway, despite its propensity to generate new people for whom they will have to take responsibility.  Sex is also that act which consummates, in the most physically and emotionally intimate or unifying way possible, those romantic relationships in which we seek to remedy our sense of incompleteness.  This adds a further, psychologically rich layer of pleasure to the act, which greatly enhances what is already intensely pleasurable just at a raw animal level.

It is not surprising, therefore, that the satisfaction this kind of pleasure promises us can lead us to do all sorts of deeply irrational things.  For just a few moments of sexual pleasure, many people will risk damage to their reputations and the breaking up of marriages and families, both their own and those of others.  Sexual or romantic passion can prevent people from seeing that a certain person is simply not a suitable marriage partner or someone with whom to have children.  Romantic and sexual jealousy can tempt people to spy on and stalk the object of their affections, or even to commit murder.  The quest for romantic and sexual pleasure can take on a compulsive character.  Hence people become promiscuous, or addicted to pornography, or prone to excessive romantic fantasizing, constantly falling in and out of love.  And of course there are various less serious ways in which romantic love or the desire for sex can lead us to act in ways we would otherwise regard as obviously foolish (ill-considered attempts to impress someone to whom one is attracted, crude sexual advances, etc.).

There is another way in which sex can lead us to act irrationally.  We can be so troubled by its tendency to make us act irrationally that we overreact to its potential dangers.  Horrified by the extremes to which some people go in the pursuit of sexual pleasure, other people sometimes tend toward the opposite extreme.  They might prudishly judge that all sexual pleasure is of its nature suspect and better avoided entirely, or at least as far as possible, even in marriage.  Even when married, they might scrupulously fret and worry over the minute details of every sexual desire or every aspect of their lovemaking, constantly in a panic over whether they have fallen into sin.  (This is, of course, much less rare a tendency these days than the opposite extreme is.  But judging from some of the oddballs you’ll find pontificating here and there on the internet, and some of the email that shows up occasionally in my combox, it does exist.  Certainly it has existed in a great many people historically.)

Everyone knows all this; once again, you don’t need to agree with traditional natural law theory to see the point.  But it is obvious that this tendency of sex to cloud our reason is of special moral significance.  What it tempts us toward is a kind of vice; naturally, then, there must also be such a thing as virtue where sex is concerned, a sober middle ground that avoids irrational extremes.  Those who reject traditional natural law theory will of course disagree with it about the specific content of virtue where matters of sex are concerned, but it simply defies reason to pretend, as Singer does, that “sex raises no unique moral issues at all.”

Indeed, people who say, in the face of all the obvious evidence, that sex is “no big deal,” thereby merely provide yet a further example of the irrationality to which we are prone in matters of sex.  For this sort of remark is, of course, typically an attempt to rationalize or excuse sexual behavior widely thought to be morally questionable but which the speaker would like to engage in anyway. 

So far I have been appealing to considerations which, as I have said, any reasonable person should agree with, whether or not he accepts everything a natural law theorist or a Catholic moral theologian would maintain vis-à-vis sexual morality.  The point is to show that one needn’t be committed wholesale to traditional sexual morality to see that sex clearly has the kind of moral significance Singer denies it does. 

But even what has been said so far goes a long way toward showing how reasonable traditional sexual morality is.  Catholic moral theology distinguishes three ends or purposes of marriage: the procreation and education of children, the mutual aid of the spouses, and the remedying of concupiscence.  It should be evident that these purposes are aimed precisely at dealing with the three respects in which sex raises special moral problems.  Sex has a propensity to result in the generation of new human beings; marriage functions to secure for these new human beings a stable environment in which their material and spiritual needs can be met.  Our desire for sexual and romantic relationships reflects our sense of being in some deep way incomplete; the institution of marriage, by which we commit ourselves to another person through thick and thin, functions to ensure that we find completion that is stable and substantive rather than ephemeral and superficial.  Sexual desire tempts us to act contrary to reason in ways that threaten to damage both ourselves and others; marriage functions to discipline sexual desire by channeling it in a way that is both socially constructive and conducive to our own best interests.

Obviously, further argumentation would be required to defend the entire range of claims Catholic moral theology and natural law theory would make about sexual morality, but that is not to the present point.  The point is rather that there is simply no basis at all for the view -- by no means unique to Singer -- that “sex raises no unique moral issues at all,” or for the common, tiresome allegation that traditional moralists’ concern with sexual morality reflects mere superstition or prudery. 

Much more can be said about the special moral problems posed by sex, from a specifically Thomistic (and thus inevitably more controversial) point of view.  But that will have to wait for a follow-up post.

612 comments:

  1. @ Chad

    You admit that most, if not all, contemporary conservatives who hold office would count as liberals with respect to your argument. In your opinion, who was (is?) the last major elected figure in the West who would count as a conservative with respect to your argument?

    I really don't know enough about politics to say. I would not claim that there are no 'conservatives' now, but I don't really know who they are. (I also think the term 'conservative' is more problematic than 'liberal'.) I actually think Republicans are generally odd beasts with a bunch of odd commitments, but I probably could not defend that claim while remaining fair to Republicans.

    For instance, lots of 'conservatives' today are willing to give totally bogus arguments appealing to free speech, freedom of religion, etc., when they are defending big, contentious conclusions. They make what are basically 'liberal' arguments, but the liberals of today gave such arguments up years ago. I see a lot of this on my campus; 'conservative' groups bring a controversial speaker, liberals go and make a big fuss, effectively silencing the speaker but not through the formal/'legal' means of the college. It's complained that the liberals are being 'intolerant,' but many who call themselves 'liberal' today are willing to say that they don't need to tolerate evil, etc.

    In other words, I don't really care to put much philosophical emphasis on any of the contemporary American political categories, since I think people rarely act on principle or care about consistency anyway.

    I think my argument in this thread could be stated in terms more specific to sexuality. For example, Girgis, Anderson, and George make their argument against same-sex marriage in terms of an opposition between a 'comprehensive' and 'conjugal' view of marriage and a 'revistionist' view of marriage. That is probably a neater way to state it, since we can divide up the American conservatives into those who would not mind revising marriage (i.e. the Koch brothers), and my argument would be that view has a tough time fending off bestiality.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Greg,
    The point is rather to emphasize that this is an odd consequence of a consent argument; what's wrong with violating something's consent is a harm to that thing.

    I think this misconstrues the argument, the wrongness isn’t that an animal’s “consent” is being violated; whatever that supposedly means for an irrational creature without moral agency, it is that that an animal clearly can’t give the right kind of consent to a moral agent. There is only one moral agent in the scenario, to focus on harm to the animal is to lose track of what is morally relevant.

    ReplyDelete
  3. @ Step2

    I think this misconstrues the argument, the wrongness isn’t that an animal’s “consent” is being violated; whatever that supposedly means for an irrational creature without moral agency, it is that that an animal clearly can’t give the right kind of consent to a moral agent. There is only one moral agent in the scenario, to focus on harm to the animal is to lose track of what is morally relevant.

    So when it is said that bestiality is bad because animals cannot consent, the point is not that bestiality harms animals? It's fine if you want to argue that, but it's odd and is not, I think, what most people (even those who believe consent rules out bestiality) mean by 'consent'.

    I have argued that there is a sense in which animals can consent. Otherwise we cannot explain cases of intercourse between animals that apparently do and don't lack consent, as we can distinguish in analogous human cases. Moreover it seems that an animal could conceivably force a human to have sex, and we cannot make sense of that without supposing that animals can in some way consent.

    Is this not "the right kind of consent"? You haven't said what the right kind of consent is. But Scott's question has to be answered: Why should the fact that an animal is an irrational creature without moral agency imply that its consent has to be respected? We don't respect animals' consent when we kill them for food or use them to get milk; it's far more plausible that animals consent to sex with a human than being brought to the slaughterhouse.

    Consequentialists would not try to dance around in this way. They would argue against the act on the basis of its harms (damages to pre-moral goods). So the violation of consent could only be wrong because they are harms to the animal. But then Singer himself is a consequentialist, and believe there are cases where bestiality does not result in a negative balance of pre-moral goods.

    Though non-consequentialist liberals will not believe that just actions are all derived from considerations of the sum of pre-moral goods, they will tend to look at harms as the relevant material for public deliberation. They (i.e. Rawls) tend to look for reasons to disqualify reasons against action that aren't based on preventing harm (in Rawls' case, to the least well off). So I am not sure what point you're trying to make. If the salient point about violations of consent is not harm to the animal, then I don't know what the point is.

    That is the sort of odd point that I detected in Chad's reasoning, though in hindsight he might not be guilty of it. What's wrong with bestiality, on the proposed understanding, is that the human is engaging sexually with an animal that can't give "the right kind of consent." If that's separable from harm to the animal, then the proposed justification does not work on liberal terms; by some variant of Mill's harm principle, it would be permissible, because the sort of wrong involved in the human's act is really a violation of himself and not (necessarily) the animal. To prohibit it would be, to the liberal, like prohibiting masturbation.

    I don't know if that is what you're proposing, but I am unsure of how else to read your comment.

    ReplyDelete
  4. Greg,
    I have argued that there is a sense in which animals can consent.

    Sure, it just isn’t a moral sense in which they consent. There isn’t any reason to doubt they can give the right kind of consent to their own kind.

    Is this not "the right kind of consent"? You haven't said what the right kind of consent is.

    I said previously adult consent was required and in light of other comments I should add sober as well.

    Consequentialists would not try to dance around in this way.

    The only dancing seems to be going on inside your head, between what I "should" say and what I am saying. I also resent be pigeon-holed as a simple consequentialist especially considering my disdain for Singer.

    If the salient point about violations of consent is not harm to the animal, then I don't know what the point is.

    The point is sex potentially can be the highest expression of intimacy. To express this towards an animal is self-degrading in a powerful way that goes deep into the uncanny valley phenomenon.

    ReplyDelete
  5. @ Step2

    I am not going to give a response since I've expressed my views at considerable length in this comment thread.

    I also resent be pigeon-holed as a simple consequentialist especially considering my disdain for Singer.

    I should note that I didn't imply that you were a consequentialist. You are clearly appealing to principles that consequentialists cannot use. I was drawing a contrast.

    ReplyDelete
  6. Crude: If I show up in a conversation about Obamacare, position myself as if I'm in favor of it, [...] and then it turns out that I actually oppose Obamacare - not just 'now' but 'ever' - how intellectually honest was my act?

    Well, it's possible to be for something and against it at the same time, in different respects. That would be where Chad's distinction between "moral systems" and "political systems" comes in (despite whatever misgivings I may have about such a distinction). Presumably it would be like, say, your claiming that you believe blasphemy is immoral, but that you also believe the government was justified in classifying blasphemy as "protected speech". You might even vote for such a law, but that wouldn't mean you really approved of blasphemy all along.

    ReplyDelete
  7. Daniel: I would be inclined treat the essence of the Person or Agent as something above and beyond the biological kind - Natural Law strikes me as a form of biological reductionism.

    I see. Well, human nature is only partly biological, and that fact that humans are rational beings suggests that meaningfulness must come into play in natural law arguments too. Neither, of course, does that rule additional factors that aren't direct consequences of natural law. I would say that the points you want to make are consistent or even part of natural law, properly understood in its general sense. To be fair, I think that people who use NL arguments do sometimes make particular appications of particular principles sound like they are Natural Law itself, rather than merely one particular attempt to draw some particular conclusion from what is really a very general foundation. (For instance, your point about man's supernatural end is a good one, but I would claim that that's a discussion about the proper account of human nature, rather than the conclusion that whatever it is, certain laws follow.)

    ReplyDelete
  8. Green,

    That would be where Chad's distinction between "moral systems" and "political systems" comes in (despite whatever misgivings I may have about such a distinction).

    I don't think this distinction works here, because feigning support for the political system is the issue. If I claim to be morally opposed to Obamacare, but insinuate myself as politically in favor of it, while actually being politically against it? The problem remains, exactly as I've put it. Put another way, insofar as the political and the moral can be separated - such that one can be politically in favor of act X while morally opposed to it - one can also be dishonest in advancing the political case.

    That's why the counter-example doesn't fly. Now, if I said, 'Gosh guys, I sure would like to outlaw blasphemy but I just don't think we have the votes. Public sentiment is against us (at 44-40 or something), we should drop this and revisit it in a hundred years.', and then it came out that I actually think outlawing blasphemy is a rotten idea, and I'd be stalwart against it even if the public was 80-20 in favor of outlawing it? Then the comparison would fly. And in that situation, you'd have caught someone bullshitting hard.

    As it stands, I have some personal interest in opposing anti-blasphemy style laws anyway, insofar as I enjoy blaspheming. It just happens to be against typically secular gods. And whatever the Episcopalians are worshiping nowadays.

    ReplyDelete
  9. Crude: If I claim to be morally opposed to Obamacare, but insinuate myself as politically in favor of it, while actually being politically against it?

    Ah, ok — being politically for something and politically against it at the same time would be some trick.

    It just happens to be against typically secular gods. And whatever the Episcopalians are worshiping nowadays.

    Ha.

    ReplyDelete
  10. Jeremy Taylor, Crude, and Mr. Green,

    I didn't answer because I would have diverged too much from the main conversation, but thanks for the replies.

    ReplyDelete
  11. I would like to say that this blog really convinced me to do it! Thanks, very good post. หนังx

    ReplyDelete
  12. It's 2021 and it's getting even less rare.

    ReplyDelete