When you
blur a real distinction between any two things A and B, you invariably tend, at
least implicitly, to deny the existence of either A or B. For instance, there is, demonstrably, a real distinction between mind and
matter. To blur this distinction, as
materialists do, is implicitly to deny the existence of mind. Reductionist materialism is, as I have argued
in several places (such as here), really just eliminative
materialism in disguise. There is also a
clear moral distinction between taking the life of an innocent person and
taking the life of a guilty person. To
blur this distinction, as many opponents of capital punishment do, is to blur
the distinction between innocence and guilt.
That is why opposition to capital punishment tends to go hand in hand
with suspicion of the very idea of punishment as such.
"One of the best contemporary writers on philosophy" National Review
"A terrific writer" Damian Thompson, Daily Telegraph
"Feser... has the rare and enviable gift of making philosophical argument compulsively readable" Sir Anthony Kenny, Times Literary Supplement
Selected for the First Things list of the 50 Best Blogs of 2010 (November 19, 2010)
Thursday, September 26, 2013
Friday, September 20, 2013
Some questions on the soul, Part I
In a
recent post I spoke of the soul after death as essentially the human being
in a “radically diminished state.” The
Aristotelian-Thomistic philosophical reasons for this characterization were set
out in an
earlier post. A reader asks how I
would “answer [the] challenge that it appears the Bible suggests our souls in
communion with God are better off than those of us here alive in this ‘vale of
tears.’” After all, St. Paul says that “we
would rather be away from the body and at home with the Lord,” and Catholics
pray to the saints, who are obviously in a better state than we are. Isn’t this clearly incompatible with the claim
that the soul after death is in a “radically diminished state”? Furthermore, wouldn’t the conscious
experiences that Christian doctrine attributes to the saved and the damned after
death be metaphysically impossible on an Aristotelian-Thomistic conception of
the soul? Wouldn’t a Cartesian view of
the soul be more in harmony with Christianity?
Do we have here a case “where Aristotelian philosophy is just at odds
with revealed Christian truth”?
Tuesday, September 17, 2013
Midwest Studies in Philosophy
My article
“The New Atheists and the Cosmological Argument” appears in Volume
37 of Midwest
Studies in Philosophy. The theme of the volume is “The New
Atheism and its Critics” and the other contributors are A. W. Moore, Michael
Ruse, David Shatz, Gary Gutting, Kenneth A. Taylor, Andrew Winer, Richard
Fumerton, Jonathan L. Kvanvig, Gregg Ten Elshof, Massimo Pigliucci, and Alister
E. McGrath.
Saturday, September 14, 2013
Man is Wolff to man
As a
follow-up to my
series of posts on the critics of Thomas Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos, let’s take a look at philosopher Robert Paul
Wolff’s recent
remarks about the book. Wolff is not
nasty, as some of the critics have been -- Nagel is Wolff’s “old friend and
one-time student” -- but he is nevertheless as unfair to Nagel as some of them
have been.
Most of his
post is not about Nagel at all, but consists of an anecdote about Edward O.
Wilson and some remarks about the wealth of knowledge Wolff has found in the
biology books he’s read. The point is to
illustrate how very meticulous good scientists can be, and how much they have
discovered about the biological realm.
All well and good. But so
what? What does that have to do with
Nagel?
Monday, September 9, 2013
The return of final causality
I commend to
you the late historian of philosophy Paul Hoffman’s paper “Does
Efficient Causation Presuppose Final Causation?
Aquinas vs. Early Modern Mechanism.”
The paper appeared in the 2009 volume Metaphysics and the Good: Themes from the Philosophy of Robert Merrihew
Adams, edited by Samuel Newlands and Larry Jorgensen, and I am pleased to
find that it is available online. It is
part of a growing number of works by contemporary thinkers outside the Thomistic
orbit which sympathetically reconsider or even defend (as Hoffman does) something
like an Aristotelian conception of teleology.
Friday, September 6, 2013
Churchland on dualism, Part V
Paul
Churchland has just published a
third edition of Matter and Consciousness,
his widely used introductory textbook on the philosophy of mind. The blog Philosophy of Brains has posted a
symposium on the book, with contributions from Amy Kind, William Ramsey,
and Pete Mandik. Prof. Kind, who deals
with Churchland’s discussion of dualism, is kind to him indeed -- a little too
kind, as it happens. Longtime readers
will recall a series of posts I did several years ago on the previous edition
of Churchland’s book, in which I showed how extremely superficial, misleading,
and frankly incompetent is its treatment of dualism. Prof. Kind commends Churchland’s “clear
writing style and incisive argumentation” as “a model for us all.” While I agree with her about the clarity of
Churchland’s style, I cannot concur with her judgment of the quality of the
book’s argumentation, for at least with respect to dualism, this new edition is
as bad as the old.