There are no
such things as tables, only “particles arranged tablewise.” Or so say certain contemporary metaphysicians,
who in the name of science deny the existence of the ordinary objects of our
experience. In her book Ordinary
Objects, philosopher Amie Thomasson rebuts such arguments. (Her work is part of a recent salutary trend,
which includes Crawford Elder’s Familiar
Objects and their Shadows and Kathrin Koslicki’s The
Structure of Objects.) Thomasson
is interviewed over
at 3:AM Magazine.
"One of the best contemporary writers on philosophy" National Review
"A terrific writer" Damian Thompson, Daily Telegraph
"Feser... has the rare and enviable gift of making philosophical argument compulsively readable" Sir Anthony Kenny, Times Literary Supplement
Selected for the First Things list of the 50 Best Blogs of 2010 (November 19, 2010)
Saturday, June 29, 2013
Wednesday, June 26, 2013
Geach on worshipping the right God
In his essay
“On Worshipping the Right God” (available in his collection God
and the Soul), Catholic philosopher Peter Geach argues that:
[W]e dare not be complacent about
confused and erroneous thinking about God, in ourselves or in others. If anybody’s thoughts about God are sufficiently
confused and erroneous, then he will fail to be thinking about the true and
living God at all; and just because God alone can draw the line, none of us is
in a position to say that a given error is not serious enough to be harmful. (p. 112)
How
harmful? Well, if a worshipper is not
even thinking about the true God, then
he is not really worshipping the true
God, but something else. That’s pretty
serious. (I would add to Geach’s concern
the consideration that atheistic objections to erroneous conceptions of God can
lead people falsely to conclude that the notion of God as such is suspect. That’s pretty serious too.)
Friday, June 21, 2013
Mind and Cosmos roundup
My series of
posts on the critics of Thomas Nagel’s Mind
and Cosmos has gotten a fair amount of attention. Andrew Ferguson’s cover
story on Nagel in The Weekly Standard,
published when I was six posts into the series, kindly cited it as a “dazzling…
tour de force rebutting Nagel’s critics.”
Now that the series is over it seems worthwhile gathering together the
posts (along with some related materials) for easy future reference.
Tuesday, June 18, 2013
Nagel and his critics, Part X
It’s time at
long last to bring my
series of posts on the critics of Thomas Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos to a close, before it becomes a lot longer than the
book itself. There isn’t, in any event,
much more to say about the naturalist critics, most of whom raise objections
similar to those on which I’ve already commented. But I’ve long intended to finish up the
series with a post on reviewers coming at Nagel’s book from the other, theistic
direction. So let’s turn to what John
Haldane, William Carroll, Alvin Plantinga, and J. P. Moreland have said about Mind and Cosmos.
Though
objecting to materialist forms of naturalism, Nagel agrees with his naturalist
critics in rejecting theism. All of the
reviewers I will comment on in this post think he does so too glibly. Naturally, I agree with them. However, as longtime readers of this blog
know, the arguments and ideas often lumped together under the “theism” label are
by no means all of a piece. Thomists and
other Scholastics develop their conception of God and arguments for his
existence on metaphysical foundations derived from Aristotelian and Neoplatonic
philosophy. But most contemporary philosophers
of religion do not, relying instead on metaphysical assumptions deriving from
the modern empiricist and rationalist traditions which defined themselves in
opposition to Aristotelianism and Scholasticism. This is a difference that makes a difference
in the reviews of Nagel now under consideration. Haldane and Carroll, like me, are Thomists, and
their approach to Nagel reflects that fact.
But the objections raised by Moreland and Plantinga are to a significant
extent different from the sort a Thomist would make.
Tuesday, June 11, 2013
Body movin’, mind thinkin’
The human body is the best picture of
the human soul.
Ludwig
Wittgenstein, Philosophical
Investigations
We recall that John B. Watson did not
claim that quite all thought was incipient speech; it was all incipient twitching of muscles, and mostly of speech muscles.
W. V. Quine,
“Mind and Verbal Dispositions”
We're getting down computer action
Do the robotic satisfaction
Do the robotic satisfaction
Beastie
Boys, “Body Movin’”
To perceive
a human being behaving in certain
characteristic ways just is to perceive him as thinking. There are two
ways to read such a claim: Quine’s and Watson’s reductionist way, and
Wittgenstein’s anti-reductionist way.
The Beastie Boys, of course, were putting forward a
computational-functionalist variation on Quinean behaviorism. (OK, not really. Just pretend.
It’s a better quote than any I could have gleaned from a functionalist
philosopher.)
Wednesday, June 5, 2013
Naturalism in the news
On the subject
of naturalism, Raymond Tallis opines
in The Guardian, Massimo Pigliucci
reports at Philosophy Now, and Daniel Dennett is interviewed at 3:AM Magazine. James Ladyman, co-author of the influential Every
Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized, gets a prominent mention in
each piece. Which gives me an excuse for
some photoshopping fun (with apologies both to Ladyman and to Tim Meadows).
Sunday, June 2, 2013
Mackie’s argument from queerness
In his book Ethics:
Inventing Right and Wrong, J. L. Mackie famously put forward his
“argument from queerness” against the objectivity of moral values. The argument has both a metaphysical aspect
and an epistemological aspect. Mackie
writes:
If there were objective values, then
they would be entities or qualities or relations of a very strange sort,
utterly different from anything else in the universe. Correspondingly, if we were aware of them, it
would have to be by some special faculty of moral perception or intuition,
utterly different from our ordinary ways of knowing everything else. (p. 38)
Mackie’s
claim is that we simply have no good reason to believe either in such odd
entities as objective values or in an odd special faculty of moral
knowledge. We can explain everything
that needs to be explained vis-à-vis morality by analyzing values in terms of
our subjective responses to certain events in the world, and Ockham’s razor
favors this approach to the alternative given the latter’s “queerness.”